Skip to main content
Log in

Tannakian duality over Dedekind rings and applications

  • Published:
Mathematische Zeitschrift Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We establish a duality between flat affine group schemes and rigid tensor categories equipped with a neutral fiber functor (called Tannakian lattice), both defined over a Dedekind ring. We use this duality and the known Tannakian duality due to Saavedra to study morphisms between flat affine group schemes. Next, we apply our new duality to the category of stratified sheaves on a smooth scheme over a Dedekind ring R to define the relative differential fundamental group scheme of the given scheme and compare the fibers of this group scheme with the fundamental group scheme of the fibers. When R is a complete DVR of equal characteristic we show that this category is Tannakian in the sense of Saavedra.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Specially locally finite coalgebras are called IFP coalgebras in [17, I.3.11].

References

  1. André, Y.: Différentielles non commutatives et Théorie de Galois différentielle ou aux différences. Ann. Scient. Ec. Norm. Sup., 4 serie, t. 34, pp. 685–739 (2001)

  2. Artin, M., Grothendieck, A., Verdier, J.L.: Théorie des topos et cohomologie étale des schémas. Lecture Note in Math., 269, 270, p. 305. Springer (1972)

  3. Bruguières, A.: On a Tannakian theorem due to Nori. http://www.math.univ-montp2.fr/~bruguieres/docs/ntan.pdf. Accessed 13 Oct 2017

  4. Bourbaki, N.: Algebre Commutative, Chapter 1–4. Springer (2006)

  5. Deligne, P., Milne, J.: Tannakian Categories, Lecture Notes in Mathematics 900, pp. 101–228. Springer (1982)

  6. Deligne, P.: Catégories tannakiennes. The Grothendieck Festschrift, vol. II, pp. 111–195, Progr. Math. 87. Birkhäuser (1990)

  7. Demazure, M., Grothendieck, A.: Propriétés Generales des Schemas en Groupes (SGA III). Expose VI\(_{\text{B}}\), Lecture Notes in Mathematics, p. 151. Springer (1970)

  8. dos Santos, J.P.P.: Fundamental group schemes for stratified sheaves. J. Algebra 317, 691–713 (2007)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. dos Santos, J.P.P.: The behavior of the differential Galois group on the generic and special bres: a Tannakian approach. J. Reine Angew. Math. 637, 63–98 (2009)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. dos Santos, J.P.P.: The homotopy exact sequence for the fundamental group schemes and infinitesimal equivalence relations. Algebraic Geom 2(5), 535–590 (2015)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. Duong, N.D., Hai, P.H., dos Santos, J.P.P.: On the structure of affine flat groups schemes over discrete valuation rings, p. 151. Preprint (2015). arXiv:1701.06518

  12. Esnault, H., Hai, P.H.: The Gauß-Manin connection and Tannaka duality. IMRN, vol. 2006, Article ID. 93978, pp. 1–35 (2006)

  13. Esnault, H., Hai, P.H.: The fundamental group schemes and applications. Ann. Inst. Fourier 58(7), 2381–2412 (2008)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  14. Esnault, H., Hai, P.H., Sun, X.: On Nori’s Fundamental Group Scheme. Geometry and Dynamics of Groups and Spaces, 377398, Progr. Math., vol. 265. Birkhäuser, Basel (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Gabriel, P.: Des catégories abéliennes. Bull. Soc. Math. Fr. 90, 323–448 (1962)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Gieseker, D.: Flat vector bundles and the fundamental group in non-zero characteristics. Ann. Sc. Norm. Super. Pisa Cl. Sci. (4) 2(1), 1–31 (1975)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. Hashimoto, M.: Auslander-Buchweitz Approximations of Equivariant Modules. London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series, vol. 282. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2000)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  18. Hai, P.H.: Gauss–Manin stratification and stratified fundamental group schemes. Ann. Inst. Fourier 63(6), 2267–2285 (2013)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  19. Hai, P.H.: On an injectivity lemma in the proof of Tannakian duality. J. Algebra Appl. 15(9), 1650167 (2016)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  20. Jantzen, J.C.: Representations of Algebraic Groups. Pure and Applied Mathematics, vol. 131. Academic Inc., Boston (1987)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  21. Katz, N.: Nilpotent connections and the monodromy theorem: applications of a result of Turrittin. Publ. Math. IHES 39, 175–232 (1970)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  22. Matsumura, H.: Commutative Ring Theory. Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics, Cambridge (1986)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  23. Moore, J.C.: Compléments sur les algébres de Hopf. Séminaire H. Cartan, 12(1), exp. 4, 1–12 (1959-1960)

  24. Saavedra Rivano, N.: Catégories Tannakiennes. Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 265. Springer, Berlin (1972)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  25. Serre, J.-P.: Groupe de Grothendieck des schémas en groupes réductifs déployés. Publ. Math. 34, 37–52 (1968)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  26. The Stacks Project Authors, Stacks Project. http://stacks.math.columbia.edu (2015). Accessed 13 Oct 2017

  27. Szamuely, T.: Galois Groups and Fundamental Groups. Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics, 117 (2009)

  28. Waterhouse, W.C.: Introduction to Affine Group Schemes. Springer, New York (1979)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  29. Wedhorn, T.: On Tannakian duality over valuation rings. J. Algebra 282, 575–609 (2004)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  30. Weibel, C.: An Introduction to Homological Algebra. Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics, vol. 38. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1994)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The second named author would like to thank H. Esnault and J.P. dos Santos for their interests in the work and very helpful discussions. He would also like to express his gratitude to J.-P. Serre for explaining him about flat coalgebras.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nguyen Dai Duong.

Additional information

Dedicated to Hélène Esnault, with admiration and affection.

This research is funded by Vietnam National Foundation for Science and Technology Development (NAFOSTED) under Grant number 101.04-2016.19. Part of this work has been carried out when the second named author was visiting the Vietnam Institute for Advanced Study in Mathematics.

Appendix A. Tannakian duality for flat coalgebras over Dedekind rings

Appendix A. Tannakian duality for flat coalgebras over Dedekind rings

In this appendix we give a quick, complete and self-contained proof of Theorem 1.2.2. First we will recall the notion ind-category of an abelian category. The two equivalent descriptions of the ind-category will play a crucial role in Saavedra’s proof. A category \({\mathcal {I}}\) is called a filtered category if to every pair ij of objects in \({\mathcal {I}}\) there exists an object k such that \(\mathsf{Hom}(i, k)\) and \(\mathsf{Hom}(j, k)\) are both not empty, and for every pair \(u, v : i \longrightarrow j,\) there exists a morphism \(w: j \longrightarrow k \) such that \(wu = wv.\)

Definition A.1.1

Ind-categories. Let \({\mathcal {C}}\) be an abelian category. The category \(\mathsf{Ind}({\mathcal {C}})\) consists of functors \(X: {\mathcal {I}} \longrightarrow {\mathcal {C}},\) where \({\mathcal {I}}\) is a filtering category. We usually denote \(X_i\) for \(X(i), i \in {\mathcal {I}},\) an write

$$\begin{aligned} X=\varinjlim _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}} X_i. \end{aligned}$$

For two objects \(X= \varinjlim _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}}X_i\) and \(Y = \varinjlim _{j\in {\mathcal {J}}}{Y_j } \) their hom-set is defined to be

$$\begin{aligned} \mathsf{Hom}(X,Y):= \displaystyle \varprojlim _{i\in {\mathcal {I}}} \displaystyle \varinjlim _{j\in {\mathcal {J}}} \mathsf{Hom}(X_i, Y_j). \end{aligned}$$

\(\square \)

Let \(\omega : {\mathcal {C}} \longrightarrow {\mathcal {D}}\) be a functor. The extension of \(\omega , \mathsf{Ind}(\omega ): \mathsf{Ind({\mathcal {C}})} \longrightarrow \mathsf {Ind}({\mathcal {D}})\) is defined by

$$\begin{aligned} \mathsf{Ind}(\omega )(\displaystyle \varinjlim _i {X_i}) := \displaystyle \varinjlim _i {\omega (X_i)}. \end{aligned}$$

There is an alternative description of \(\mathsf{Ind}({\mathcal {C}})\). Denote \(\mathsf{Lex}({\mathcal {C}}^{op}, {\mathcal Sets})\) the category of left exact functors from \({\mathcal {C}}^{op}\) to the category of sets. For \(X= \varinjlim _i X_i\) we define functor

$$\begin{aligned} \displaystyle \varinjlim _i h_{X_i}(-):= \displaystyle \varinjlim _i \mathsf{Hom}(-, X_i) \in \mathsf{Lex}({\mathcal {C}}^{op}, {\mathcal Sets}). \end{aligned}$$

This yields a functor \( \mathsf {Ind({\mathcal {C}})} \longrightarrow \mathsf{Lex}({\mathcal {C}}^{op}, {\mathcal Sets})\) which is an equivalence (cf.[2], I.8.3.3). Recall that the Hom-sets for objects of \(\mathsf{Lex}({\mathcal {C}}^{op}, {\mathcal Sets})\) are by definition the sets of natural transformations. For simplicity, we shall use the notation \(\mathsf{Hom}(F,G)\) instead of \(\mathsf{Nat}(F,G)\) for objects of this category.

A.1.2. Suppose that \({\mathcal {C}}\) is an R-linear Noetherian abelian category. Let \(\mathsf{Lex}_R({\mathcal {C}}^{op}, \mathsf{Mod}(R))\) be category of R-linear left exact functors from \({\mathcal {C}}^{op}\) to the category of modules \(\mathsf{Mod}(R)\). Then the natural functor

$$\begin{aligned} \mathsf{Lex}_R({\mathcal {C}}^{op}, \mathsf{Mod}(R)) \xrightarrow {\ \simeq \ }\mathsf{Lex}({\mathcal {C}}^{op}, {\mathcal Sets}) \end{aligned}$$

is an equivalence (cf. Gabriel [15, II]). Thus, for an R-linear Noetherian abelian category we have an equivalence

$$\begin{aligned} \mathsf{Ind}({\mathcal {C}})\simeq \mathsf{Lex}_R({\mathcal {C}}^{op}, \mathsf{Mod}(R)),\quad X=\varinjlim _iX_i\longmapsto \displaystyle \varinjlim _i h_{X_i}(-). \end{aligned}$$

Further the category \(\mathsf{Ind}({\mathcal {C}})\) is locally Noetherian and the inclusion \({\mathcal {C}}\longrightarrow \mathsf{Ind}({\mathcal {C}})\) identifies \({\mathcal {C}}\) with the full subcategory of Noetherian objects in \(\mathsf{Ind}({\mathcal {C}})\), [15, II, 4, Thm. 1].

The following are our main examples.

Example A.1.3

The category \(\mathsf{Mod}_{\mathrm{f}}(R)\) of finitely generated R-modules, where R is a Noetherian ring, is a Noetherian category. Its Ind category is precisely the category \(\mathsf{Mod}(R)\) of all R-modules. This is obvious.

Example A.1.4

Let L be a coalgebra over a commutative ring R. Denote by \(\mathsf{Comod}(L)\) the category of right L-comodules and by \(\mathsf{Comod}_{\mathrm{f}}(L)\) the subcategory of comodules which are finitely generated as R-module. Then:

  1. (i)

    If L is flat over R then \(\mathsf{Comod}(L)\) is an abelian category. In fact, the flatness of L implies that the kernel of a homomorphism of L-comodules is equipped with a natural coaction of L. In particular, the forgetful functor from \(\mathsf{Comod}(L)\) to \(\mathsf{Mod}(R)\) is exact. The converse is also true: if the forgetful functor preserves kernels then L is flat over R.

  2. (ii)

    Assume that L is flat over R and R is Noetherian. According to Serre [25, Cor. 2] each L-comodule is the union of its R-finite subcomodules. Consequently, \(\mathsf{Comod}(L)\) is locally Noetherian and \(\mathsf{Comod}_{\mathrm{f}}(L)\) is the full subcategory of Noetherian objects.

Let \({\mathcal {C}}\) be an R-linear abelian category, and \(\omega : {\mathcal {C}} \longrightarrow \mathsf{Mod}_{\mathrm{f}}(R)\) be an R-linear exact faithful functor. Suppose that there exists a full subcategory of definition \({\mathcal {C}}^{\mathrm{o}}\) in \({\mathcal {C}}.\) Our aim is to show that there exists a flat R-coalgebra L such that \(\omega \) induces an equivalence between \(\mathsf{Comod}_{\mathrm{f}}(L)\) and \({\mathcal {C}}\), and between \(\mathsf{Comod}(L)\) and \(\mathsf{Ind}({\mathcal {C}})\).

The functor \(\omega \) induces a functor \( \mathsf{Ind}( {\mathcal {C}})\longrightarrow \mathsf{Mod}(R),\) which we, by abuse of language, will denote simply by \(\omega \). Recall that we identify \(\mathsf{Ind}({\mathcal {C}})\) with \(\mathsf{Lex}({\mathcal {C}}^{op}, \mathsf{Mod}(R))\), the category of left exact functors on \({\mathcal {C}}^{op}\) with values in \(\mathsf{Mod}(R)\). The key technique is to use alternatively these two equivalent descriptions of one category.

A.1.5. For any R-algebra A, we define functor

$$\begin{aligned} F^A: {\mathcal {C}}^{op} \longrightarrow \mathsf{Mod}(A),\quad X \longmapsto \mathsf{Hom}( \omega (X), A). \end{aligned}$$

Then \(F^A\) is an object of \( \mathsf{Lex}({\mathcal {C}}^{op}, \mathsf{Mod}(R))\). Set \(F:=F^R\). There is a natural A-linear transformation \(A\otimes F\longrightarrow F^A\):

$$\begin{aligned} \theta _X:A\otimes \mathsf{Hom}(\omega (X),R)\longrightarrow \mathsf{Hom}(\omega (X),A),\quad a\otimes f\longmapsto af. \end{aligned}$$

Lemma A.1.6

The A-linear transformation \(\theta :A\otimes F\longrightarrow F^A\) given above is an isomorphism.

Proof

For any \(K, G \in \mathsf{Lex}({\mathcal {C}}^{op}, \mathsf{Mod}(R))\) we denote \(K^{\mathrm{o}}, G^{\mathrm{o}}\) their restrictions to \(({\mathcal {C}}^{\mathrm{o}})^{op}\), respectively. We claim that

$$\begin{aligned} \mathsf{Hom}(K,G) \simeq \mathsf{Hom}(K^{\mathrm{o}}, G^{\mathrm{o}}). \end{aligned}$$
(14)

Indeed, let \(\theta \in \mathsf{Hom}(K^{\mathrm{o}}, G^{\mathrm{o}})\), that is we have a family \(\theta _X:K^{\mathrm{o}}(X)\longrightarrow G^{\mathrm{o}}\) for \(X\in {\mathcal {C}}^{\mathrm{o}}\) commuting with morphism in \({\mathcal {C}}^{\mathrm{o}}\). Since each object of \({\mathcal {C}}\) can be represented as a cokernel of a morphism \(X_1\longrightarrow X_2\) in \({\mathcal {C}}^{\mathrm{o}}\), we see that \(\theta \) extends uniquely to a natural transformation \(K\longrightarrow G\) (as these functors are left exact on \({\mathcal {C}}^{\mathrm{op}}\)).

For \(X\in {\mathcal {C}}^{\mathrm{o}}\), \(\omega (X)\) is finite projective over R, hence

$$\begin{aligned} F^A(X) =\mathsf{Hom}(\omega (X), A) \simeq \mathsf{Hom}(\omega (X), R) \otimes A = A \otimes F(X). \end{aligned}$$

Therefore, for any \(G\in \mathsf{Lex}({\mathcal {C}}^{op}, \mathsf{Mod}(R))\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} \mathsf{Hom}((F^A)^{\mathrm{o}}, G^{\mathrm{o}}) = \mathsf{Hom}((A\otimes F)^{\mathrm{o}}, G^{\mathrm{o}}) \end{aligned}$$
(15)

and (14) yields

$$\begin{aligned} \mathsf{Hom}(F^A, G) = \mathsf{Hom}(A\otimes F, G). \end{aligned}$$
(16)

So we have \(F^A\simeq A \otimes F.\) \(\square \)

We will show that \(L:=\omega (F)\) is the coalgebra to be found. To show this, first we will need

Lemma A.1.7

For any \(X\in \mathsf{Lex}({\mathcal {C}}^{op},\mathsf{Mod}(R))\) and R-algebra A we have the following A-linear isomorphism:

$$\begin{aligned} \mathsf{Hom}(X, F^A) \simeq \mathsf{Hom}_A(A\otimes \omega (X), A)=\mathsf{Hom}_R( \omega (X), A). \end{aligned}$$
(17)

Proof

Every \(X \in \mathsf{Lex}({\mathcal {C}}^{op},\mathsf{Mod}(R))\) can be represented as \(X= \displaystyle \varinjlim _i h_{X_i} ( X_i \in {\mathcal {C}}),\) where \(h_{X_i}\) is a functor over \({\mathcal {C}}\), defined by \(h_{X_i}(-) := \mathsf{Hom}_{{\mathcal {C}}}( -, X_i).\) Hence we have

$$\begin{aligned} \mathsf{Hom}(X, F^A)= & {} \mathsf{Hom}( \varinjlim h_{X_i},F^A)\\= & {} \varprojlim \mathsf{Hom}(h_{X_i}, F^A)\\= & {} \varprojlim F^A (X_i) \\= & {} \mathsf{Hom}_R( \varinjlim \omega (X_i), A)\\= & {} \mathsf{Hom}_R(\omega (\varinjlim h_{X_i}), A)\\= & {} \mathsf{Hom}_R( \omega (X), A). \end{aligned}$$

It is easy to see that all isomorphisms are A-linear. \(\square \)

Isomorphism (17) for \(A=R\) and \(X=F\) reads \(\mathsf{Hom}(F,F)\simeq \mathsf{Hom}_R(\omega (F),R)\). We denote \(L:=\omega (F)\) and let \(\varepsilon :L\longrightarrow R\) be the map on the right hand side that corresponds to the identity transformation on the left hand side of this isomorphism. The next lemma shows that one can replace the algebra A in (17) by any R-module M to get R-linear isomorphisms.

Lemma A.1.8

There exists a natural R-linear isomorphism extending (17)

$$\begin{aligned} \Phi _{X,M}: \mathsf{Hom}(X,M\otimes F) \simeq \mathsf{Hom}_R(\omega (X), M), \end{aligned}$$
(18)

which is given explicitly by

$$\begin{aligned} \Phi _{X,M}(f)= (\mathsf{id}_M\otimes \varepsilon )\circ \omega (f). \end{aligned}$$

Proof

For any R-module M, we can make \(R\oplus M\) into an R-algebra by letting M be an ideal with square null. Hence the isomorphism (18) is a direct consequence of (17). By definition \(\Phi _{F,R}\) is given by

$$\begin{aligned} \Phi _{F,R}(f)=\varepsilon \circ \omega (f). \end{aligned}$$

Each R-linear map \(\iota :R\longrightarrow M\) induces by functoriality the commutative diagram

Now, the identity on F yields the equality:

$$\begin{aligned} \iota \circ \varepsilon =\Phi _{F,M}(\iota \otimes \mathsf{id}_{\omega (F)}):\omega (F)\longrightarrow M. \end{aligned}$$

Hence, for \(m=\iota (1)\), we have \(\Phi _{F,M}(l)=\varepsilon (l)m\), \(l\in \omega (F)\). Thus the claim holds for \(X=F\). Since the \(\omega \) and Hom-functor in the first variant commute with direct limits we conclude that the claim hold of \(X=N\otimes F\) for any R-module N. Now the general case follows from the following diagram

applied for the identity of \(M\otimes F\):

$$\begin{aligned} \Phi _{X,M}(f)=\Phi _{F,M}(\mathsf{id})\circ \omega (f)=(\mathsf{id}_M\otimes \varepsilon )\circ \omega (f). \end{aligned}$$

\(\square \)

Proposition A.1.9

Let \(L:=\omega (F)\). Then it is a coalgebra with \(\varepsilon \) being the counit and \(\omega \) factors though a functor

$$\begin{aligned} \mathsf{Ind}({\mathcal {C}})\longrightarrow \mathsf{Comod}(L). \end{aligned}$$

Proof

Choose \(M= \omega (X)\) in (18) we have a morphism \( {\sigma }_X :X \longrightarrow \omega (X) \otimes F\) which corresponds to the identity element \(\mathsf{id}_{\omega (X)}\) under the isomorphism \(\Phi _{X,\omega (X)}\) of Lemma A.1.8, thus we have

$$\begin{aligned} (\mathsf{id}_{\omega (X)} \otimes \varepsilon ) \circ \omega (\sigma _{X}) = \mathsf{id}_{\omega (X)}. \end{aligned}$$
(19)

For any morphism \(\lambda : X \longrightarrow Y\) in \(\mathsf{Ind}( {\mathcal {C}})\), according to A.1.8 we have the following equalities:

$$\begin{aligned}&\Phi _{X,\omega (Y)}\left( (\omega (\lambda ) \otimes \mathsf{id}_ {F}) \circ \sigma _X\right) =\omega (\lambda ),\\&\Phi _{X,\omega (Y)}\left( \sigma _Y \circ \lambda \right) = \omega (\lambda ). \end{aligned}$$

Thus \((\omega (\lambda ) \otimes \mathsf{id}_{F}) \circ \sigma _X= \sigma _Y \circ \lambda ,\) i.e, the following diagram commutes:

(20)

For \(Y=\omega (X)\otimes F\) and \(\lambda =\sigma _X\), we get

(21)

Applying \(\omega \) on this diagram we obtain a commutative diagram in \(\mathsf{Mod}(R)\):

(22)

where \(\Delta :=\omega (\sigma _F)\). Together with (19), this diagram for \(X=F\) gives a coalgebra structure on L with \(\Delta \) being the coproduct and hence, for any X, it gives a comodule structure of L on \(\omega (X)\). \(\square \)

Proof (of Theorem 1.2.2)

Let L be defined as in Proposition A.1.9. We consider \(\omega \) as a functor \({\mathcal {C}}\longrightarrow \mathsf{Comod}_{\mathrm{f}}(L)\). It is to show that \(\omega \) is an equivalence of category. By definition it is faithful. To see the fullness, suppose \(X, Y \in {\mathcal {C}}\) and \(\alpha : \omega (X) \longrightarrow \omega (Y)\) is a homomorphism of L-comodules, i.e., we have

$$\begin{aligned} (\alpha \otimes \mathsf{id})\circ \omega (\sigma _X)=\omega (\sigma _Y)\circ \alpha :\omega (X)\longrightarrow \omega (Y)\otimes L. \end{aligned}$$

Then is the image under \(\omega \) of the morphism

Notice that (22) (for X replaced by Y) yields a split exact sequence

(23)

where the second homomorphism is \(\delta =\mathsf{id}\otimes \Delta -\omega (\sigma _X)\otimes \mathsf{id},\) and the splitting is given by \(\mathsf{id}\otimes \varepsilon :\omega (Y)\otimes L\longrightarrow \omega (Y).\) This sequence is the similar image under \(\omega \) of the sequence coming from (21):

$$\begin{aligned} 0\longrightarrow Y\longrightarrow \omega (Y) \otimes F\longrightarrow \omega (Y) \otimes L \otimes F. \end{aligned}$$

Hence the latter sequence is also exact. On the other hand, it follows from the faithfulness of \(\omega \) that the composed map

is the zero morphism (since its image under \(\omega \) is zero by means of (22) and the fact that \(\alpha \) is a homomorphism of L-comodules). Consequently, the morphism factor through a morphism \(f:X\longrightarrow Y\) and the morphism \(\sigma _Y\). Applying \(\omega \) on the composition of these maps we conclude \(\omega (f)=\alpha \), as \(\omega (\sigma _Y)\) is injective. Thus \(\omega \) is full.

It remains to show that \(\varphi \) is essentially surjective. For any L-comodule \((E,\rho _E)\) let \(E^{\mathrm{o}} \in C\) be such that the sequence

$$\begin{aligned} 0\longrightarrow E^{\mathrm{o}}\longrightarrow E \otimes F\xrightarrow {\quad \delta } E \otimes L \otimes F. \end{aligned}$$

is exact, where \(\delta =\rho _E\otimes \mathsf{id}-\mathsf{id}\otimes \sigma _F\). Applying \(\omega \) to this sequence and comparing with (23) we conclude that \(\omega (E^{\mathrm{o}})=E\).

Thus \(\omega :{\mathcal {C}}\longrightarrow \mathsf{Comod}_{\mathrm{f}}(L)\) is an equivalence of categories. Thus the forgetful functor \(\mathsf{Comod}_{\mathrm{f}}(L)\longrightarrow \mathsf{Mod}(R)\) is exact, hence L is flat over R. \(\square \)

Remarks A.1.10

(i) Under the equivalence of Theorem 1.2.2, L, with the right coaction of itself given by the coproduct, corresponds to F. Indeed, this follows from the natural isomorphism

$$\begin{aligned} \mathsf{Hom}^L(E,L)\simeq \mathsf{Hom}_R(E,R),\quad f\mapsto \varepsilon \circ f. \end{aligned}$$

(ii) There is another way to determine L from the category of its comodules as follows. We claim that there is a natural isomorphism

$$\begin{aligned} \mathsf{Nat}(\omega ,\omega \otimes M)\simeq \mathsf{Hom}_R(L,M), \end{aligned}$$
(24)

for any R-module M. Indeed, we have

$$\begin{aligned} \mathsf{Hom}_R(L,M)\simeq \mathsf{Hom}(F,F\otimes M)\simeq \mathsf{Hom}(\mathsf{Hom}(\omega ,R),\mathsf{Hom}(\omega ,R)\otimes M). \end{aligned}$$

By means of (14), it suffices to show the isomorphism

$$\begin{aligned} \mathsf{Nat}(\omega (X),\omega (X)\otimes M)\simeq \mathsf{Hom}(\mathsf{Hom}(\omega (X),R),\mathsf{Hom}(\omega (X),R)\otimes M) \end{aligned}$$

for any \(X\in {\mathcal {C}}^{\mathrm{o}}\). Since for such X, \(\omega (X)\) is finitely generated projective over R, the last isomorphism is obvious. L is usually referred to as the Coend of \(\omega \), denoted \(\mathsf{Coend}(\omega )\).

(iii) If \({\mathcal {C}}=\mathsf{Comod}_{\mathrm{f}}(L)\) and \(\omega \) is the forgetful functor from \({\mathcal {C}}\) to \(\mathsf{Mod}(R)\), then the isomorphism (24) implies that \(\mathsf{Coend}(\omega )\simeq L\). Thus a flat coalgebra over R can be reconstructed from the category of its comodules. \(\square \)

Remarks A.1.11

Let \(({\mathcal {C}},\omega )\) and \(({\mathcal {C}}',\omega ')\) be two categories satisfying the condition of Theorem 1.2.2 and let \(\eta :{\mathcal {C}}\longrightarrow {\mathcal {C}}'\) be an R-linear functor such that \(\omega '\eta =\omega \). Then \(\eta \) induces a coalgebra homomorphism \(f:L\longrightarrow L'\). This can be seen from (24) as follows. The coaction of \(L'\) on \(\omega '(X')\) defines a natural transformation \(\delta ':\omega '\longrightarrow \omega '\otimes L'\). Combine this with \(\eta \) we obtain a natural transformation \(\delta :\omega \longrightarrow \omega \otimes L'\). Thus (24) yields a linear map \(L\longrightarrow L'\), which satisfies the following commutative diagram:

\(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Duong, N.D., Hô Hai, P. Tannakian duality over Dedekind rings and applications. Math. Z. 288, 1103–1142 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00209-017-1928-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00209-017-1928-6

Mathematics Subject Classification

Navigation