Skip to main content
Log in

Opportunist politicians and the evolution of electoral competition

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
Journal of Evolutionary Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper studies a uni-dimensional model of electoral competition between two parties with two types of politicians. ‘Opportunist’ ones care only about the spoils of the office, and ‘militant’ ones have ideological preferences on the policy space. Opportunist politicians review their affiliations and may switch parties, seeking better election prospects. In this framework, we compare a winner-take-all system, where all the spoils of office go to the winner, to a proportional system, where the spoils of office are split among the two parties in proportion to their vote shares. We study the existence of short term political equilibria and the dynamics and stability of policies and of party membership decisions. In the long run, it is possible that proportional systems see opportunist politicians spread over all parties, but this situation is unstable in winner-take-all systems.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. On this point, Downs (1957) follows the “economist” description of electoral competition after Hotelling (1929) or Black (1948). The view that parties and politicians are ideology-motivated is in the tradition of Michels (1915) or Lipset (1959) and is formalized by Wittman (1983), Hansson and Stuart (1984), and Calvert (1985). Note that, in Roemer (1999), there is a third faction, the so-called reformists, who maximize the expected utility of their party constituents. We do not include the reformist faction in our model.

  2. The rationalistic approach to game theory assumes that players are perfectly rational, the game is played once and the game and its equilibria are common knowledge. On the other hand, the evolutionary approach assumes that boundedly rational players who are randomly drawn from large populations and who have little or no information about the game, play the game repeatedly. Thus, the evolutionary approach allows us to analyze a game theoretic situation when we relax perfect information and unbounded rationality assumptions. The main difference between these approaches is that the rationalistic approach analyzes the individual behavior while the evolutionary approach analyzes the population distribution of behaviors (strategies). Classically, in biology, the analysis of population dynamics includes two processes: the selection process favoring better performing strategies and the mutation process introducing varieties. Non-biological interpretations of evolutionary game theory have been proposed. Börgers and Sarin (1997) and Laslier et al. (2001) show that models of individual learning-by-reinforcement can be approximated by replicator dynamics. Björnerstedt and Weibull (1996) show that the replicator dynamics may be derived from a number of learning-by-imitation models, where revising individuals imitate other individuals. Schlag (1998) shows that a behavioral rule that outperforms the other improving rules is the one where agents imitate the action of an observed individual, and that when each individual imitates, the aggregate population behavior is, again, approximated by replicator dynamics.

  3. In Roemer (2001), it has been also shown that when each party works out a method of inner-party bargaining, the policy proposal that they reach as a consequence of inner-party bargaining is a PUNE since, at that proposal, no party faction would agree to deviate to another policy.

  4. The formal results are provided in the Appendix.

  5. Notice that the same ideas (and the same mathematical model) could also be interpreted in terms of the renewal of party composition through the continuous arrival of young politicians and retirement of elder ones. For simplicity, we stick to one interpretation, in terms of politicians changing sides rather than differential attraction to beginners.

  6. A variety of payoff monotonicity conditions have been proposed in the literature. Nachbar (1990) proposes sign-preserving dynamics satisfying relative monotonicity where the population shares of strategies with above average payoffs grow, while those of strategies with payoff below average shrink. Samuelson and Zhang (1992) define regular selection dynamics that require the growth rates of strategies to have the same ranking as their respective payoffs; this condition of monotone growth rate is referred to as monotonicity. The more general class of dynamics satisfying weakly payoff positive monotonicity proposed by Weibull (1995) requires that at least one strategy that earns more than the average has a positive growth rate. This class of selection dynamics includes the replicator dynamics (Taylor and Jonker 1978). In the present context, since there are only two strategies, all of the above classes of dynamics are equivalent and induce monotonic selection dynamics.

  7. Here, we can refer to asymptotic stability or Liapunov stability, because the dynamics is in one dimension only. (See Hirsch and Smale 1974.)

  8. We obtain the following quadratic equation: (2ns + l)(2(1−m)(1−l) + m(2ns + l))−4(1−l)2(l + ns)=0. As δ = 16(1−2l)2(1−l)2(l 2 + m 2)>0, this equation has two roots: \({s}_{1}^{\ast }=\frac {1}{2}\left (1+\frac {(1-l)(l-\sqrt {l^{2}+m^{2}})}{m(-1+2l)}\right )\) and \(s^{\ast }_{2}=\frac {1}{2}\left (1+\frac {(1-l)(l+\sqrt {l^{2}+m^{2}})}{m(-1+2l)}\right )\). For m = 0, there is only one root \(s^{\ast } = \frac {1}{2}\) as Eq. 10 is linear. As, for m ∈[−1,1]−0, \(|s^{\ast }_{2}|>1\), there is at most one root in the unit interval. Regarding \({s}_{1}^{\ast }\), the stability constraints depicted in Fig. 2 apply. Above the dotted curve, \({s}_{1}^{\ast }<0\) and below the dashed curve, \(s^{\ast }_{1}>1\). Between these curves, this root is in the unit interval.

  9. Note that, when s = 1 (s = 0), all opportunists are in party L (R) and the policy proposal of party R (L) is made only by the militants and therefore is constant.

  10. Myerson (1993) assumes that some parties are exogenously corrupt while the others are not, and shows that proportional elections are better for the voters than majoritarian elections, because voters can choose not to vote for corrupt parties without compromising their partisan preferences. Using a sample of more than fifty democracies, Persson and Tabellini (1999) find that spending on public goods as a percentage of GDP is lower in countries with majoritarian elections. Milesi-Ferretti et al. (2002) study the relationship between the size and composition of government spending and different measures of proportionality, using a panel data set for government spending in the OECD countries from the 1960s onward; they find that transfer payments are strongly positively related to the degree of proportionality.

References

  • Aldrich J, Bianco W (1992) A game theoretic model of party affiliation of candidates and office holders. Math Comput Model 16:103–116

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alesina A, Spear SE (1988) An overlapping generations model of electoral competition. J Public Econ 37:359–379

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black D (1948) On the rationale of group decision-making. J Polit Econ 56:23–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Björnerstedt J,Weibull J (1996) Nash equilibrium and evolution by imitation. In: Arrow K, et al. (eds) The rational foundations of economic behaviour, Macmillan, New York

  • Börgers T, Sarin R (1997) Learning through reinforcement and replicator dynamics. J Econ Theory 77:1–14

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowler S, Farrell DM, Katz RS (1999) Party cohesion, party discipline and parliaments. In: Bowler S, Farrell DM, Katz RS (eds) Party discipline and parliamentary government. Ohio State University Press, Columbus, pp 3–22

  • Bratton M (2013) Voting and democratic citzenship in Africa. Lynne Rienner, Boulder

    Google Scholar 

  • Calvert R (1985) Robustness of the multidimensional voting model, candidate motivations, uncertainty, and convergence. Am J Polit Sci 39:69–95

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Desposato S (2006) Parties for rent? Ambition, ideology and party switching in Brazils chamber of deputies. Am J Polit Sci 50:62–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Marchi S (1999) Adaptive models and electoral instability. Journal of Theoretical Politics 11:393–419

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downs A (1957) An economic theory of democracy. Harper Collins, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Engels J, Stroth A, Wantchekon L (2008) Le fonctionnement des partis politiques au Bénin. Friedrich Ebert Stiftung, Cotonou

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenno RF (1973) Home Style. Boston, Little-Brown

    Google Scholar 

  • Grose CR, Yoshinaka A (2003) The electoral consequences of party switching by incumbent members of congress 1947–2000. Legis Stud Q 28:55–75

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson I, Stuart C (1984) Voting competitions with interested politicians: platforms do not converge to the preferences of the median voter. Public Choice 44:431–441

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller WB, Mershon C (2009) Integrating theoretical and empirical models of party switching. In: Heller WB, Mershon C (eds) Political parties and legislative party switching. PalgraveMacmillan, New York, pp 29–51

  • Hirsch MW, Smale S (1974) Differential equations, dynamical systems, and linear algebra. Academic Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hotelling H (1929) Stability in competition. Econ J 39:41–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huber JD, Powell GB (1994) Congruence between citizens and policymakers in two visions of liberal democracy. World Politics 46:291–326

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kollman K, Miller JH, Page SE (1992) Adaptive parties in spatial elections. Am Polit Sci Rev 86:929–937

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kollman K, Miller JH, Page SE (1998) Political parties and electoral landscapes. Br J Polit Sci 28:139–158

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kollman K, Miller JH, Page SE (2003) Computational models in political economy. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Laslier JF, Topol R, Walliser B (2001) A behavioral learning process in games. Games and Economic Behavior 37:340–366

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laver M (2005) Policy and the dynamics of political competition. Am Polit Sci Rev 99:263–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laver M, Benoit K (2003) The Evolution of Party Systems between Elections. Am J Polit Sci 47:215–233

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lijphart A (1999) Patterns of democracy: government forms and performance in thirty-six countries. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipset SM (1959) Political Man. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • McElroy G (2003) Party switching in the European parliament: why bother? Presentation at the 2003 meeting of the European consortium for political research, Marburg, Germany

  • Mershon C, Shvetsova O (2014) Change in parliamentary party systems and policy outcomes: hunting the core. Journal of Theoretical Politics 26:331–351

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michels R (1915) Political parties: a sociological study of oligarchical tendencies in modern democracy. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Milesi-Ferretti G-M, Perotti R, Rostagno M (2002) Electoral systems and public spending. Q J Econ 117:602–657

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson R (1993) Effectiveness of electoral systems for reducing government corruption: a game theoretic analysis. Games and Economic Behavior 5:118–132

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nachbar JH (1990) Evolutionary selection dynamics in games: convergence and limit properties. Int J Game Theory 19:59–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien DZ, Shomer Y (2013) Legislators’ motivations, institutional arrangements, and changes in partisan affiliation: a cross-national analysis of party switching. Legis Stud Q 38:111–141

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Persson T, Tabellini G (1999) Political economics and macroeconomic policy. In: Taylor J., Woodford M. (eds) Handbook of Macroeconomics. Amsterdam, North-Holland

  • Powell GB (2000) Elections as instruments of democracy: majoritarian and proportional visions. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Powell GB (2006) Election laws and representative governments: beyond votes and seats. Br J Polit Sci 36:291–315

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roemer JE (1999) The democratic political economy of progressive taxation. Econometrica 67:1–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roemer JE (2001) Political competition: theory and applications. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson L, Zhang J (1992) Evolutionary stability in asymmetric games. J Econ Theory 57:363–391

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlag K (1998) Why imitate, and if so, how? A bounded rational approach to multi-armed bandits. J Econ Theory 78:130–156

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1954) Bandwagon and underdog effects and the possibility of election predictions. Public Opin Q 18:245–253

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stadelmann D, Portmann M, Eichenberger R (2013) Preference representation and the influence of political parties in majoritarian vs. proportional systems: an empirical test. CREMA working paper series 2013-03, Center for research in economics, management and the arts (CREMA)

  • Taylor P, Jonker L (1978) Evolutionarily stable strategies and game dynamics. Math Biosci 40:145–156

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weibull J (1995) Evolutionary game theory. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittman D (1983) Candidate motivation: a synthesis of alternative theories. Am Polit Sci Rev 77:142–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jean-François Laslier.

Additional information

We thank for their comments Ludovic Rheault, Matías Núñez, and a referee of this journal.

Appendix A

Appendix A

1.1 A.1 The two-stage game for the electoral competition

In this section, we analyze the model as a static two-stage game. We consider now that at the first stage, opportunist politicians can all change their membership and at the second stage, party platforms are determined. We analyze the case where all the opportunists are in party L or in party R. Note that the following utilities apply at the second stage:

$$u_{L}(t_{L}(s),t_{R}(s)) = \frac{1}{l+ns}F(t^{eq}(s)) $$
$$u_{R}(t_{L}(s),t_{R}(s))=\frac{1}{r+n(1-s)}(1-F(t^{eq}(s))) $$

where \(t^{eq}(s)=\frac {2nsr+lr}{2\left (lr+n(l(1-s)+sr)\right )}\).

The opportunists will choose either party L or party R. In order to see which party the opportunists prefer, we have to analyze the difference of the utility of being in party L when all opportunists affiliate with party L and the utility of being in party R when they all choose party R. Let Δ = u L (t L (1), t R (1))−u R (t L (0), t R (0)). Then we have the following result:

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} {\Delta} &=& \frac{1}{l+n}F\left( t^{eq}(1)\right)-\frac{1}{r+n} \left( 1-F(t^{eq}(0))\right))\\ &=& \frac{1}{(1-r)}F\left( \frac{2n+l}{2\left( 1-r\right) } \right)+\frac{1}{(r+n)}F\left( \frac{r}{2(r+n)} \right)-\frac{1}{(r+n)}. \end{array} $$

Drawing the previous function for different distributions of voters, one obtains Fig. 8, which describes the region where the utility of being in party L when all opportunists choose party L is larger than the utility of being in party R when all choose party R. The region is defined according to the number of opportunist politicians and militants in party R. In the region below the solid line in Fig. 8, opportunists will prefer party R when citizens are uniformly distributed along the unit line.

Fig. 8
figure 8

Gain from switching from party R to party L, for uniform and skewed distributions of voters

For a distribution skewed to the left or to the right, the frontier moves to the left and to the right accordingly. Switching from party R to party L is less likely to be beneficial when voters are distributed more to the right. In Fig. 8, the area below the curves shrinks as the distribution of voters changes from a mostly leftist to a mostly rightist population. Let n = 0.4, r = 0.4, l = 0.2. One can see that all the opportunists will choose to be affiliated with party L only when citizens are distributed uniformly or more to the left.

If the distribution of voters is uniform and there are equal numbers of militants in each party, then Δ = u L (t L (1), t R (1))−u R (t L (0), t R (0))=0. In that case the opportunist politicians will be indifferent between affiliating with one party or the other. Even though the case where they are distributed equally may be one of the equilibrium for the stage game, it is not an evolutionary stable outcome.

1.2 A.2 Proof of Proposition 1

(Proposition 1) In the proportional system, the state where all opportunists are in party L (that is s = 1) is asymptotically stable if G(1)>0. The state where all opportunists are in party R (that is s = 0) is asymptotically stable if G(0)<0.

To prove Proposition 1, we need to first prove the following lemma.

Lemma 1

Given a monotonic selection dynamics ξ, a population state sis asymptotically stable if

$$(2s-1)\left( u_{L}\left( {t}_{L}^{eq}(s),{t}_{R}^{eq}(s)\right)-u_{R}\left( {t}_{L}^{eq}(s),{t}_{R}^{eq}(s)\right)\right)>0. $$

Proof

Let s =0. If \((2s^{\ast }-1) \left (u_{L}\left ({t}_{L}^{eq} (s^{\ast }), {t}_{R}^{eq} (s^{\ast })\right ) - u_{R} \left ({t}_{L}^{eq} (s^{\ast }), {t}_{R}^{eq} (s^{\ast })\right )\right )>0\) , then \(u_{L} \left ({t}_{L}^{eq} (s^{\ast }), {t}_{R}^{eq} (s^{\ast })\right ) < u_{R} \left ({t}_{L}^{eq} (s^{\ast }), {t}_{R}^{eq}(s^{\ast })\right )\). By continuity of the payoffs with respect to the population share, there exists a neighborhood \(\mathcal {N}\) of s such that, for all \(s\in \mathcal {N} \setminus \{s^{\ast }\}\), \(u_{L} \left ({t}_{L}^{eq}(s), {t}_{R}^{eq}(s)\right ) < u_{R}\left ({t}_{L}^{eq}(s), {t}_{R}^{eq}(s)\right )\). If the dynamics ξ(s) are monotonic, then \(\dot {s}<0\). Let L(s)=1−s. L(s) attains its maximum value of 1 when s = s , and is positive and increasing in \(\mathcal {N} \setminus \{ s^{\ast } \}\). This is a strict Liapunov function for s and s is asymptotically stable by Liapunov’s Stability Theorem. □

Let s =1, the condition writes: \(u_{L} \left ({t}_{L}^{eq} (s^{\ast }), {t}_{R}^{eq} (s^{\ast })\right ) > u_{R} \left ({t}_{L}^{eq} (s^{\ast }), {t}_{R}^{eq} (s^{\ast })\right )\). By continuity, there exists a neighborhood \(\mathcal {N}\) of s such that, for all \(s\in \mathcal {N} \setminus \{s^{\ast } \}\), \(u_{L} \left ({t}_{L}^{eq} (s), {t}_{R}^{eq} (s)\right ) > u_{R} \left ({t}_{L}^{eq} (s), {t}_{R}^{eq}(s)\right )\). If the dynamics ξ(s) are monotonic, then \(\dot {s} > 0\). Let L(s) = s, L(s) attains its maximum value of 1 when s = s , and is positive and increasing in \(\mathcal {N} \setminus \{ s^{\ast }\}\). This is a strict Liapunov function for s and s is asymptotically stable.

Proof Proof of the Proposition

The lemma simply says that s = 1 is stable if u L (.)>u R (.) and s = 0 is stable if u L (.)<u R (.). Thus, s = 1 is stable if G(1)>0 and s = 0 is stable if G(0)<0. □

Notice that the conditions are not tight. A more explicit version of these conditions is as follows:

For s = 1 to be asymptotically stable we need the following condition:

$$u_{L} \left( {t}_{L}^{eq}(1), {t}_{R}^{eq}(1)\right) - u_{R} \left( {t}_{L}^{eq}(1), {t}_{R}^{eq}(1)\right) >0. $$

The difference can be written:

$$\frac{1}{l+n}F(t^{eq}(1))-\frac{1}{r}(1-F(t^{eq}(1))) = \frac{F(t^{eq}(1))-l-n}{(l+n)r}, $$

hence the condition:

$$F(t^{eq}(1))>l+n. $$

For s = 0 to be asymptotically stable, we obtain in the same manner the following condition:

$$\frac{F(t^{eq}(0))-l}{(r+n)l}>0\Rightarrow F(t^{eq}(0))>l. $$

1.3 A.3 Proof of Proposition 2

(Proposition 2) In the proportional system, if G (s)<0 in the unit interval, G(0)>0, and G(1)<0, then there is a unique, asymptotically stable mixed state.

Proof

Rest points of the evolutionary dynamics require all surviving strategies to have equal payoffs. Then, an interior rest point s ∈(0,1) requires that \(u_{L} \left ({t}_{L}^{eq} (s^{\ast }), {t}_{R}^{eq} (s^{\ast })\right ) = u_{R} \left ({t}_{L}^{eq} (s^{\ast }), {t}_{R}^{eq}(s^{\ast })\right )\). Computation shows that:

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} &&u_{L}\left( t_{L}^{eq}(s^{\ast}),t_{R}^{eq}(s^{\ast})\right)-u_{R}\left( t_{L}^{eq}(s^{\ast}),t_{R}^{eq}(s^{\ast})\right)\\ &&\qquad = \frac{1}{l+ns^{\ast}}F\left( t^{eq}(s^{\ast})\right)-\frac{1}{r+n(1-s^{\ast})}\left( 1-F(t^{eq}(s^{\ast}))\right)\\ &&\qquad = \frac{F\left( t^{eq}(s^{\ast})\right)-l-ns^{\ast}}{(r+n(1-s^{\ast}))(l+ns^{\ast})}. \end{array} $$

The condition is thus:

$$F(t^{eq}(s^{\ast}))=l+ns^{\ast}. $$

The interior rest points are roots of this equation.

If payoffs are continuous at any state z and G (⋅)<0 in the unit interval then, for z = s 𝜖, \(u_{L} \left ({t}_{L}^{eq}(z), {t}_{R}^{eq}(z)\right ) > u_{R} \left ({t}_{L}^{eq} (z), {t}_{R}^{eq}(z)\right )\), and for z = s + 𝜖, \(u_{L} \left ({t}_{L}^{eq}(z), {t}_{R}^{eq}(z)\right ) < u_{R} \left ({t}_{L}^{eq}(z), {t}_{R}^{eq}(z)\right )\). Let \(\mathcal {N} (\epsilon ) = \left [ s^{\ast } - \epsilon , s^{\ast } + \epsilon \right ]\). For any 𝜖>0, we have \(s \in \mathcal {N}(\epsilon )\). Hence \(\mathcal {N}(\epsilon )\) is an invariant set: any trajectory originating in \(\mathcal {N}(\epsilon )\) remains there forever. Moreover, for all \(s \in \mathcal {N}(\epsilon )\), all trajectories originating in \(\mathcal {N}(\epsilon )\) converge to some rest point z. But since G (⋅)<0, G(0)>0 and G(1)<0, by the intermediate value theorem, there is a unique rest point of this type, at z = s , and all trajectories originating in \(\mathcal {N}(\epsilon )\) converge to this point, which is asymptotically stable. □

1.4 A.4 Proof of Proposition 3

(Proposition 3) In the winner-take-all system, the graph of the probability of victory, as we have defined it, is not continuous. There is at most one solution to the Eq. 11. There are three cases to analyze...

Proof

Note that s = 1 is stable if u L (⋅)>u R (⋅) and that s = 0 is stable if u L (⋅)<u R (⋅). □

Case 1

\(t_{min}=\frac {r}{2(r+n)} \leq t^{med}\leq \frac {2n+l}{2(l+n)}=t_{max}\). If all opportunists are in party L, then t eq(0) = t min and \(\pi \left (t_{L}^{eq}(0),t_{R}^{eq}(0)\right )=0\), and we have:

$$\begin{array}{lll} u_{L}\left( t_{L}^{eq}(0),t_{R}^{eq}(0)\right) &=& \frac{1}{l}\pi\left( t_{L}^{eq}(0),t_{R}^{eq}(0)\right)=0\\ &<& u_{R}\left( t_{L}^{eq}(0),t_{R}^{eq}(0)\right) =\frac{1}{r+n}\left( 1-\pi \left( t_{L}^{eq}(0),t_{R}^{eq}(0)\right)\right) = \frac{1}{r+n}. \end{array} $$

If all opportunists are in party R, then t eq(1) = t max and \(\pi \left (t_{L}^{eq}(1),t_{R}^{eq}(1)\right )=1\) , and we have \(u_{L}\left (t_{L}^{eq}(1),t_{R}^{eq}(1)\right )=\frac {1}{l+n}\pi \left (t_{L}^{eq}(1),t_{R}^{eq}(1)\right )=\frac {1}{l+n}>u_{R}\left (t_{L}^{eq}(1),t_{R}^{eq}(1)\right )= \frac {1}{r}\left (1-\pi \left (t_{L}^{eq}(1),t_{R}^{eq}(1)\right )\right )=0\). These states will both be stable. Let s M be the solution to the Eq. 11. Then s M must satisfy the following conditions: t eq(s M) = t med and \(l+ns^{M}=\frac {1}{2}\). From the previous results, s M will not be stable.

Case 2

t med<t min . Then t med is always smaller than t eq(s), \(\pi \left (t_{L}^{eq}(s),t_{R}^{eq}(s)\right )=1\) and the utility of being a member of party L is always larger than affiliating with party R. The case where all the opportunists are in party L (that is s = 0) is the only stable state.

Case 3

t med>t max . Then t med is always larger than t eq(s), \(\pi (t_{L}^{eq}(s),t_{R}^{eq}(s))=0\) and being a member of party R has always more utility than being a member of party L. The case where all the opportunists are in the party R (that is s = 1) is the only stable state.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Laslier, JF., Ozturk Goktuna, B. Opportunist politicians and the evolution of electoral competition. J Evol Econ 26, 381–406 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00191-016-0444-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00191-016-0444-x

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation