Skip to main content
Log in

Intentionality and the emergence of complexity: an analytical approach

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
Journal of Evolutionary Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Emergence is a generic property that makes economies become complex. The simultaneous carrying out of agents’ intentional action plans within an economic system generates processes that are at the base of structural change and the emergence of adaptive complex systems. This paper argues that goals and intentionality are key elements of the structure of rational human action and are the origin of emergent properties such as innovation within economic complex systems. To deal with the locus and role of goals and intentionality in relation to the emergence of complexity we propose an analytical approach based on agents’ action plans. Action plans are open representations of the action projected by agents (as individuals or organizations), where the means (actions) and objectives (or goals) are not necessarily given, but produced by agents themselves.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Emergence is a key generic property that makes economies become complex (Harper and Endres 2012).

  2. A good classic precedent in philosophy is Ascombe (1957). An interesting approach quite complementary to ours is Bratman’s (1987 [1999], 1999). (See also Bratman et al. (1988).) An interesting review is Zimmerman (1989).

  3. In a quite related field, Arthur (2007, 2009) has stressed the purposeful character of (actions that give rise to) invention and technical development.

  4. Fuster (2003, 2008) physiologically locates action plans in the prefrontal cortex of humans.

  5. For example a family’s travel plans, the business or production plans of a company, etc.

  6. The concept of action plan has been used with different formalization by economists as diverse as Lachmann (1994 [1976]), Keynes (1936), Hicks (1939), Stackelberg (1946 [1943]), Barnard (1938), Debreu (1959), Penrose (1959), Malinvaud (1999), Boulding (1991), etc.

  7. Culture, defined as in North (2005), plays a fundamental role in economic change.

  8. Investigation cannot pre-exclude plans that contain systems of goals that are internally inconsistent. In fact, these kinds of plans may form part of the reality under study and constitute an interesting field of study in themselves. See for example Encinar (2002).

  9. As far as plans are components of a bundle, and are intrinsically linked together forming a whole course of action, each pattern of bundling may be understood as an attempt at tentative modularization of action by the agent. The plans that form the bundle (three plans in Fig. 2) would be themselves quasi-decomposable modules of a higher level “system” of actions-goals –the bundle- that would direct the future course of action of the agent. For the meaning of quasi-decomposability and modularization see, respectively, Simon (1962) and Langlois (2002).

  10. The new goal psychology represents a step forward in the integration of motives for action with psychological theories, generally cognitive, on human action. The links are the very goals or objectives of the action. See various chapters in the Oxford Handbook of Human Action (Morsella et al.2009), especially those included in part 2 (dedicated to the activation, selection and expression of action) and in Moskowitz and Grant (2009). On motivation in Economics see Frey and Jegen (2001) and Gerschlager (2012).

  11. Subsections 3.1 and 3.2 are grounded and develop the approach by Rubio de Urquía (2005) introducing intentionality within the analytical framework.

  12. This bundle in a neoclassical account would roughly correspond to the bundle that maximises some objective function (utility, profits, etc.). However, in a more general (and realistic, that is, where true uncertainty prevails) framework the agent chooses bundles that “meet targets of adequacy rather than pinnacles of attainment” (Earl 1983: 78–81). It is very interesting to compare our analytical stages with those proposed respectively by Earl and Potts. The former (Earl 1983: 149-150) presents a multistage process in which the agent proceeds sequentially as follows: (1) problem recognition (a failure to match up to aspirations), (2) search of (not given) courses of action, (3) evaluation of possible sequels of particular choices, (4) choice itself, (5) implementation (often difficult and partially accomplished), and (6) assessment (the agent examines to which extent what was decided was achieved). Potts (2000: 120–123) addresses the problem of acting in a non-integral space. Agents must form conjectures as a solution by means of searching among adjacent possibilities which relationships may solve (are more promising ways of solving) their particular problems. The ‘decision cycle’ that makes these operations possible consists of four separate components: {LIST, CONSTRUCT, RANK, SELECT}. The main point in Potts’ proposal is that, for him, these conjectures are the agents’ preferences (note the conjectural character of action plans).

  13. The ensemble refers to the “reality” such as it is conceived by the agents in order to produce their action.

  14. The term “beliefs” refers to the set of conceptions, representations and knowledge to which the individual is faithful. In general, beliefs imply evaluation criteria that organize the projective action and the action of decision among alternatives and value judgments. “Values” is understood as the set of valuation criteria effectively used by the individual to projectively organize the action and issue value judgments. The possible difference between the valuation criteria implied by the beliefs and those effectively used in practice must be acknowledged. Values include tastes and preferences. “Attitudes” refers to stable features that introduce determination in certain aspects.

  15. In our approach, the symbol → neither represents a logical relationship (for example a material conditional if-then relationship) nor a mathematical function that relates two (or more) variables (as is the case of a production function, for instance). It designates a mode -that is, a conventional sign- of representing a necessary causal relationship among theoretical structures. Quite a different issue is that in some very specific circumstances it is possible to characterize parts of a theory of human action by means of proper (not imposed) mathematical structures as is the case of neoclassical economics under highly restrictive theoretical assumptions.

  16. This stage is rather similar to the one that Earl (1983: 150) has called “assessment” in his multistage process model of choice.

  17. The agent’s state may include explicitly the agent’s “biography”; the set of all the states of all the individuals other than i prior to time t that may influence the agent.

  18. They could be unplanned actions due to, for example, the use of routines, rules, procedures and behavioural habits, which also generate consequences, expected or otherwise, in action.

  19. At t it may be that n t n t−1 or that n t <n t−1.

  20. How individuals set goals, etc., is very important for other disciplines such as psychology. (See for instance, Ajzen 1991; Miller et al. 1960; Moskowitz and Grant 2009).

  21. New in the sense of “unheard-of”.

  22. Owing to this, novelties cannot be uncaused causes as Hodgson (2004, chap. 3) suggests: the ultimate cause is the intentionality of agents. In an example provided by Schumpeter’s (2005 [1932]) Mantegna’s innovations could be interpreted as a conscious and individual act undertaken by the painter; the ‘Renaissance style’ produced unexpected innovations in painting as a result of painters interactions.

  23. As has been said above, in economics the simplest example of ΔS is a perfect-competition market; in this structure of interaction –in which agents, agents’ goals, and structure of interaction do not change- the consequences ΔS are expressed in terms of the complex of produced and consumed quantities and the equilibrium price. Of course ΔS may be more complex: we may think that there is rationing equilibria (Benassy 1986; Malinvaud 1977); non-market interactions (Schelling 1978); network effects (Katz and Shapiro 1994); etc.

  24. Examples include the analysis of the origin and evolution of techno-economic innovation systems, the emergence of technological clusters, the evolution of institutions, etc.

  25. The role of beliefs, etc. has been recognised in economic theory. Recently, Acemoglu has pointed out that the fundamental causes of economic growth are luck, geographical differences, institutional differences and “cultural differences that determine individuals’ values, preferences and beliefs” (Acemoglu 2009: 20).

  26. It must be stressed that the aim of this paper is not to offer a technical solution to a particular problem. It is an analytical proposal intended to make tractable North’s (2005) and Loasby’s (2012) challenges, i.e.: to erect scaffoldings (analytical frameworks) that allow us to deal with human interaction and the sources of complexity (and structural change) -scaffoldings being able to accommodate, at the same time intentionality and different “ecologies of plans” (Wagner 2012).

References

  • Acemoglu D (2009) Introduction to modern economic growth. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Ajzen I (1991) The theory of planned behavior. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process 50:179–211

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson PW, Arrow KJ, Pines D (1988) The economy as an evolving complex system. Addison-Wesley, Reading

  • Antonelli C (2011) The economic complexity of technological change: knowledge interaction and path dependence. In: Antonelli C (ed) Handbook on the economic complexity of technological change. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, pp 3–59

  • Antonelli C, Ferraris G (2011) Innovation as an emerging system property: an agent based simulation model. J Artif Soc Soc Simul 14(2):47

    Google Scholar 

  • Arthur WB (1990) Positive feedbacks in the economy. Sci Am 262:92–99

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arthur WB (2007) The structure of invention. Res Policy 36:274–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arthur WB (2009) The nature of technology. What it is and how it evolves. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ascombe GEM (1957) Intention. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin DA, Baird JA (2001) Discerning intentions in dynamic human action. Trends Cogn Sci 5(4):171–178

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnard C (1938) The functions of the executive. Harvard UP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Benassy JP (1986) Macroeconomics: an introduction to the non-walrasian approach. Academic, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhattacharyya A, Pattanaik PK, Xu Y (2011) Choice, internal consistency and rationality. Econ Philos 27(2):123–149

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blume LE, Durlauf SN (eds) (2006) The economy as an evolving complex system, III: current perspectives and future directions. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Boulding K (1991) What is evolutionary economics? J Evol Econ 1(1):9–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman ME (1987 [1999]) Intention, plans, and practical reason. CSLI Publications, Standford

  • Bratman ME (1999) Faces of intention. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman ME, Israel DJ, Pollack ME (1988) Plans and resource-bounded practical reasoning. Comput Intell 4(3):349–355

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brentano F (1874) Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt. Duncker & Humblot, Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • Cañibano C, Encinar MI, Muñoz FF (2006) Evolving capabilities and innovative intentionality: some reflections on the role of intention within innovation processe. Innov Manag Policy Pract 8(4–5):310–321

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Debreu G (1959) Theory of value. An axiomatic analysis of economic equilibrium. Cowles foundation monograph, p 17

  • Dopfer K (2011) Evolution and complexity in economics revisited. Papers on Economics & Evolution Max Planck Institute of Economics, Evolutionary Economics Group, Jena

  • Dopfer K, Foster J, Potts J (2004) Micro–meso–macro. J Evol Econ 14(3):263–279

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earl PE (1983) The economic imagination. Towards a behavioural analysis of choice. Wheatsheaf Books, Brighton

    Google Scholar 

  • Encinar MI, Muñoz FF (2006) On novelty and economics: Schumpeter’s paradox. J Evol Econ 16(3):255–277

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Encinar MI (2002) Análisis de las propiedades de “consistencia” y “realizabilidad” en los planes de acción Una perspectiva desde la teoría Económica. Universidad Autónoma de Madrid, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Felin T, Foss NJ (2009) Organizational routines and capabilities: historical drift and a course-correction toward microfoundations. Scand J Manag 25:157–167

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frey BS, Jegen R (2001) Motivation crowding theory. J Econ Surv 15(5):589–611

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuster JM (2003) Cortex and mind Unifying cognition. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuster JM (2008) The prefrontal cortex, 4th edn. Academic, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerschlager C (2012) Agents of change. J Evol Econ 22:413–441

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grosz BJ, Hunsberger L (2006) The dynamics of intention in collaborative activity. Cogn Syst Res 7:259–272

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hands DW (2001) Reflection without rules. Economic methodology and contemporary science theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harper DA, Endres AM (2012) The anatomy of emergence, with a focus upon capital formation. J Econ Behav Organ 82(2–3):352–367

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hicks JR (1939) Value and capital: an inquiry into some fundamental principles of economic theory. Clarendon Paperbacks, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM (2004) The evolution of institutional economics. Routledge, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2007) Evolutionary theorizing beyond lamarckism: a reply to Richard Nelson. J Evol Econ 17(3):353–359

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2011) Agreeing on generalised Darwinism: a response to Pavel Pelikan. J Evol Econ 1–10

  • Katz ML, Shapiro C (1994) Systems competition and network effects. J Econ Perspect 8(2):93–115

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly GA (1963) A theory of personality. W.W. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes JM (1936) The general theory of employment, interest and money. MacMillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lachmann L (1994 [1976]) From Mises to Shackle. An essay on Austrian economics and the kaleidic society. In: Lavoie D (ed) Expectations and the meaning of institutions. Essays in economics by Ludwig Lachmann. Routledge, London, pp 218–228

  • Lane D, Malerba F, Maxfield R, Orsenigo L (1996) Choice and action. J Evol Econ 6(1):43–76

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langlois RN (2002) Modularity in technology and organization. J Econ Behav Organ 49:19–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levit G, Hossfeld U, Witt U (2011) Can Darwinism be “Generalized” and of what use would this be? J Evol Econ 21(4):545–562. doi:10.1007/s00191-011-0235-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loasby BJ (1996) The imagined, deemed possibe. In: Helmstädter E, Perlman M (eds) Behavioral norms, technological progress, and economic dynamics. Michigan University Press, Michigan, pp 17–31

    Google Scholar 

  • Loasby BJ (1999) Knowledge, institutions and evolution in economics. Routledge, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Loasby BJ (2003) Closed models and open systems. J Econ Methodol 10(3):285–306

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loasby BJ (2012) Building systems. J Evol Econ 22(4):833–846

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malinvaud E (1977) The theory of unemployment reconsidered. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Malinvaud E (1999) Leçons de théorie microéconomique (4e édition). Dunod, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Malle BF, Moses LJ, Baldwin DA (eds) (2001) Intentions and intentionality: foundations of social cognition. The MIT Press, Cambridge

  • Metcalfe JS, Foster J, Ramlogan R (2006) Adaptive economic growth. Cambridge J Econ 30(1):7–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger T, Gallese V (2003) The emergence of a shared action ontology: building blocks for a theory. Conscious Cogn 12:549–571

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller GA, Galanter E, Pribram KH (1960) Plans and the structure of behavior. Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miller JH, Page SE (2007) Complex adaptive systems. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Mises L (1949) Human action: a teatrise on economics. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Morsella E, Bargh JA, Gollwitzer PM (eds) (2009) Oxford handbook of human action. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Moskowitz GB, Grant H (eds) (2009) The psychology of goals. The Guilford Press, New York

  • Muñoz FF, Encinar MI (2007) Action plans and socio-economic evolutionary change. RePec: Working Papers in Economic Theory, Universidad Autónoma de Madrid (Spain), Department of Economic Analysis, Madrid

  • Muñoz FF, Encinar MI, Cañibano C (2011) On the role of intentionality in evolutionary economic change. Struct Chang Econ Dyn 22:193–203

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson RR (2007) Comment on: dismantling Lamarckism: why descriptions of socio-economic evolution as Lamarckian are misleading, by Hodgson and Knudsen. J Evol Econ 17(3):349–352

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • North DC (2005) Understanding the process of economic change. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose ET (1959) The theory of the growth of the firm. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K (1972) Conjectures and refutations. The growth of scientific knowledge, 4th edn. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Potts J (2000) The new evolutionary microeconomics. Complexity, competence and adaptive behaviour. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins L (1932) An essay on the nature and significance of economic science, 2nd edn (1969). Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosser JB (ed) (2004) Complexity in economics. Methodology, interacting agents and microeconomic models. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

  • Rubio de Urquía R (2003) Estructura fundamental de la explicación de procesos de ’autoorganización’ mediante modelos teórico-económicos. In: Rubio de Urquía R, Vázquez FJ, Muñoz FF (eds) Procesos de autoorganización. IIES Francisco de Vitoria-Unión Editorial, Madrid, pp 13–96

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubio de Urquía R (2005) La naturaleza y estructura fundamental de la teoría económica y las relaciones entre enunciados teórico-económicos y enunciados antropológicos. In: Rubio de Urquía R, Ureña EM, Muñoz FF (eds) Estudios de Teoría Económica y Antropología. IIES Francisco de Vitoria-AEDOS-Unión Editorial, Madrid, pp 23–198

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubio de Urquía R (2011) La economía española y lo urgente: operar en los fundamentos. In: Velarde J (ed) Lo que hay que hacer con urgencia. Actas, Madrid, pp 411–438

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling T (1978) Micromotives and macrobehaviors. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter JA (2005 [1932]) Development. (Translated and with an introduction by Becker MC, EBlinger HU, Hedtka U and Knudsen T). J Econ Lit 43(1):112–120

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter JA (1947a) The creative response in economic history. J Econ Hist 7(2):149–159

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter JA (1947b) Theoretical problems: theoretical problems of economic growth. J Econ Hist 7:1–9

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (1995) The construction of social reality. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (2001) Rationality in action. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1993) Internal consistency of choice. Econometrica 61(3):495–521

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shackle GLS (1972) Epistemics and economics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Shackle GLS (1977) Time and choice. In: Proceedings of the British Academy, pp 309–329

  • Simon HA (1962) The architecture of complexity: hierarchic systems. In: Proceedings of the American philosophical society, pp 467–482

  • Stackelberg H (1946 [1943]) Principios de Teoría Económica [Grundzüge der theoretischen Volkwirschaftslehre] Spanish edition augmented, and revised by the author. Instituto de Estudios Políticos, Madrid

  • Vanberg VJ (2006) Human intentionality and design in cultural evolution. In: Schubert C, Wangenheim Gv (eds) Evolution and design of institutions. Routledge, Oxford, pp 197–212

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner RE (2012) A macro economy as an ecology of plans. J Econ Behav Organ 82(2–3):433–444

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (1996) Innovations, externalities, and the problem of economic progress. Public Choice 89:113–130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2003) The evolving economy. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

    Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2006) Evolutionary concepts in economics and biology. J Evol Econ 16(5):473–476

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman M (1989) Intention, plans, and practical reason. Philos Phenomenol Res 50(1):189–197

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to thank two anonymous referees for their very useful comments and suggestions as well as to Professor Rafael Rubio de Urquía, Carolina Cañibano and David Harper, for their valuable advises.

The authors acknowledge the scientific support from the ‘Instituto de Investigaciones Económicas y Sociales Francisco de Vitoria’ and Universidad Aut ´onoma de Madrid. The usual disclaimers apply.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Félix-Fernando Muñoz.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Muñoz, FF., Encinar, MI. Intentionality and the emergence of complexity: an analytical approach. J Evol Econ 24, 317–334 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00191-014-0342-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00191-014-0342-z

Keywords

JEL Classifications

Navigation