Advertisement

Büchner’s Danton and the Metaphysics of Atheism

  • Rodney Taylor
Article

Abstract

Disillusionment and despair represent the subjective corollaries of Damon’s revolutionary actions. In the face of his impending death he describes himself as an atheist. This self-characterization relates to a complex metaphysical conception of the universe by means of which Danton articulates the depth and magnitude of his suffering.

Zusammenfassung

Desillusionierung und Verzweiflung ergeben sich für Danton folgerichtig aus seinen revolutionären Taten. Vor seinem nahen Tode bezeichnet er sich als Atheisten. Dieses Selbstverständnis gründet in einer komplexen metaphysischen Weltauffassung, mittels derer Danton die Tiefe seines Elends zum Ausdruck bringt.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 1.
    Georg Büchner, Nachgelassene Schriften, ed. Ludwig Büchner, Frankfurt a.M. 1850, 128–129. For purposes of the present essay, Ludwig Büchner’s edition is most useful; his capitalization of the word ‘etwas” in Danton’s statements concerning the structure of the universe suggests a significant recognition of the ontological impetus of Danton’s utterances at 111.7” of his brother’s play.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Philosophie der Geschichte, Universal-Bibliothek Nr. 4811[7], Stuttgart 1980, 74–75.Google Scholar
  3. 7.
    Cf. Alfred Behrmann, Joachim Wohlleben, Büchner: Dantons Tod. Eine Dramenanalyse, LGW47 Literaturwissenschaft-Gesellschaftswissenschaft, Stuttgart 1980, 122.Google Scholar
  4. 9.
    Cf. Erwin Kobel, Georg Büchner, Berlin 1974, 63.Google Scholar
  5. 10.
    Lucius Annaeus Seneca, Moral Essays, trans. John W. Basore, 3 vols., Loeb Classical Library, Cambridge, Mass. 1965, II, 66. Basore’s English translation reads: “Death is a release from all suffering, a boundary beyond which our ills cannot pass - it restores to us that peaceful state in which we lay before we were born. If anyone pities the dead he must also pity those who have not been born. Death is neither a good nor an evil; for that only which is something is able to be a good or an evil. But that which is itself nothing and reduces all things to nothingness consigns us to neither sphere of fortune; for evils and goods must operate upon something material” (67).Google Scholar
  6. 13.
    Cf. Henry E. Allison, Benedict de Spinoza, Boston 1975, 209–210.Google Scholar
  7. 14.
    David Bell, Spinoza in Germany from 1670 to the Age of Goethe, Bithell Series of Dissertations Volume Seven, London 1980, 2–12.Google Scholar
  8. 15.
    Cf. Michael Voges’s essay entitled “Dantons Tod” in Interpretationen. Georg Büchner, Universal-Bibliothek Nr. 8415[3], Stuttgart 1990, 7–51, 47.Google Scholar
  9. 16.
    Benedictus de Spinoza, Spinoza Opera, ed. Carl Gebhardt, 4 vols., Heidelberg 1972, II, 45.Google Scholar
  10. 17.
    Spinoza (note 16), II, 45. In German, Definition 3 in Part I of the Ethica is translated as follows: “Unter Substanz verstehe ich das, was in sich ist und durch sich begriffen wird; d.h. das, dessen Begriff nicht den Begriff eines anderen Dinges nötig hat, um daraus gebildet zu werden.” Cf. Benedictus de Spinoza, Ethik, trans. Jakob Stern, Universal-Bibliothek Nr. 851[9], Stuttgart 1980, 5.Google Scholar
  11. 19.
    Cf. Ludwig Feuerbach’s illuminating chapter on Spinoza in his Geschichte der Neueren Philosophie von Bacon von Verulam bis Benedikt De Spinoza, ed. Friedrich Jodl, Stuttgart, Bad-Cannstatt 1959, 307. Here Feuerbach affirms that substance is equivalent to an eternal act of thinking (“Denken”) that betokens “ein schlechthin unbedingter und unendlicher Begriff”. Hence to be substance means to be a thing in which Thought and Being are identical.Google Scholar
  12. 20.
    Walter Hinderer, Büchner Kommentar zum dichterischen Werk, München 1977, 120.Google Scholar
  13. 22.
    Cf. Harry A. Wolfson, The Philosophy of Spinoza, 2 vols., Cambridge, Mass. 1962, I, 117–119.Google Scholar
  14. 24.
    Georg Büchner, Sämtliche Werke, Historisch-Kritische Ausgabe, ed. Werner R. Lehmann, 2 vols., Hamburg 1971, II, 237.Google Scholar
  15. 26.
    Cf. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Wissenschaft der Logik, Rheinisch-Westfälische Akademie der Wissenschaften, ed. Friedrich Hogemann and Walter Jaeschke, 2 vols., Hamburg 1978, I, 45. On the basis of its presupposition regarding the thoroughgoing distinction between Being and Nothingness established by the axiom, “Ex nihilo nihil fit,” Hegel maintains that traditional Occidental metaphysics culminates in Spinoza’s radical denial of ontological validity to the principle of Becoming.Google Scholar
  16. 27.
    Cf. Nicolai Hartmann, Philosophie der Natur, Berlin 1980, 267.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. 35.
    Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi, Leber die Lehre des Spinoza, Breslau 1785, 14.Google Scholar
  18. 35a.
    In his notes on the Presocratics, Büchner indicates strong similarities between the God of Xenophanes, the One of Parmenides, and the Spinozán divinity. For him, the Absolute described by these philosophers has its ontological source in the proposition: “Aus Nichts kann Nichts entstehen.” Cf. Büchner (note 24), II, 312–315. Buchner’s views on ancient Greek philosophy are derived from vols. I—III of Wilhelm Gottlieb Tennemann’s Geschichte der Philosophie (1798–1801). They also display parallels to Hegels identification of Parmenides’ Absolute with that of Spinoza. Cf. Hegel (note 26), I, 45–50. Both Hegel and Tennemann attribute to Parmenides as well as to Spinoza the metaphysical axiom adduced by Jacobi as the Grundsatz of Spinozism. Thus, while Büchner knew Jacobi’s work on Spinoza in its own right, his familiarity with works by Tennemann and Hegel made him aware of the monumental significance of this notion for the history of Occidental metaphysics in general. Doubtless these works also reinforced to him the value and importance of Jacobi’s Spinoza interpretation as such.Google Scholar
  19. 39.
    Johann Gottfried Herder, Sämtliche Werke, ed. Bernhard Suphan, 33 vols., Hildesheim 1967, XVI, 418.Google Scholar
  20. 54.
    I have borrowed this phrase from Francis Herbert Bradley, Appearance and Reality, 9th ed., London 1951, 148.Google Scholar
  21. 60.
    In Spinoza’s view, the human mind, as a finite mode of thought, is an idea whose formal nature perfectly mirrors the “actually existing thing” that is its body. Upon the demise of this finite mode of extension, the mind also disintegrates. Errol E. Harris writes: “For Spinoza… immortality is not an indefinitely extended after-life in which the mind persists through time after the death of the body As a finite mode of extension the body necessarily comes to an end in time and is destroyed. The mind… is dissipated in consequence when the body ceases to maintain itself.” Cf. Spinoza’s Philosophy: An Outline, New Jersey 1992, 113.Google Scholar
  22. 66.
    Cf. Elizabeth Hoffart, Herders “Gott”, Halle a.S. 1918, 45. Cf. Hegel (note 26), I, 57.Google Scholar
  23. 83.
    Samuel Beckett, Proust, New York 1970, 8–9.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Metzler 1995

Authors and Affiliations

  • Rodney Taylor
    • 1
  1. 1.KirksvilleUSA

Personalised recommendations