Advertisement

Getting over nihilism: Nietzsche, Heidegger and the appropriation of tragedy

  • James Crooks
Article
  • 185 Downloads

Abstract

The paper examines what might best be called thestructural influence of Greek tragedy on Heidegger's interpretation/criticism of Nietzsche and explores briefly some of its consequences. In doing so, it develops three interrelated theses: 1) that situating the definitively modern experience of nihilism in the intellectual paradigm of 19th-century German Hellenism, both Nietzsche and Heidegger appropriate tragedy as the narrative model of Western history, 2) that what Heidegger calls their confrontation orAuseinandersetzung arises at the level of ‘metaphysical’ dramaturgy (i.e., filling out and realizing the model), and 3) that the position that emerges out of thisAuseinandersetzung leads him back to certain discursive paradigms of Plato and Aristotle. The motivation of these arguments is to show that, ‘metaphysical’ differences notwithstanding, bot Nietzsche and Heidegger describe what they take to be the crisis of the modern world in classical terms.

Keywords

Classical Tradition Greek Tragedy Professional Classicist Loeb Classical Library Narrative Model 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 1.
    Nietzsche,Die Geburt der Tragoedie, in:Werke in drei Bänden, ed. Karl Schlechta (München: Karl Hanser Verlag, 1966) I, p. 87; trans. Francis Golffing in Nietzsche,The Birth of Tragedy and the Gennealogy of Morals (New York: Doubleday, 1956), p. 95. All page/volume numbers for Nietzsche below refer to the Schlechta edition.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Heidegger, ‘Der Spruch des Anaximander’,Holzwege (Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1963), p. 330, trans. David Farrell Krell and Frank A.Capuzzi in Heidegger, Early Greek Thinking (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1975, repr. ibid. 1984), p. 44.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Glenn Most, ‘Heidegger's Greeks,’Arion, IIIrd ser., 10.1 (Spring/Summer 2002), pp. 83–98, here p. 96.Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    James Porter,Nietzsche and the Philology of the Future (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2000), p. 254. Cf. also Thomas Heilke,Nietzsche's Tragic Regime (Dekalb: Northern Illinois University Press, 1998), pp. 66–71.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Cf. especiallyHomer's Wettkampf (III, pp. 291–300),Die Philosophie im tragischen Zeitalter der Griechen (III, pp. 349–413), andDie Geburt der Tragoedie (I, pp. 7–134).Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Cf. especiallyZur Genealogie der Moral (II, pp. 761–798).Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    III, p. 325, trans. James Porter inThe Invention of Dionysus (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2000), p. 7.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    I, p. 210, trans. ibid. James Porter inThe Invention of Dionysus (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2000), p. 62.Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    NotablySein und Zeit (1927) andKant und das Problem der Metaphysik (1929). These books are now volumes 2 and 3 of theGesamtausgabe (GA) (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1977 and 1991, respectively).Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Courses of study offered in this period include:Der Deutsche Idealismus (Fichte, Hegel, Schelling) und die philosophische Problemlage der Gegenwart, 1929 (GA, 28),Vom Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit, 1930 (GA 31),Hegels Phaenomenologie des Geistes, (GA 32) andHoelderlins Hymnen ‘Germanien’ und ‘Der Rhein’, 1934 (GA 39).Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    Cf. for example the coursesVom Wesen der Wahrheit. Zu Platons Hoehlengleichnis und Theaetet, 1931 (GA 34) andDer Anfang der abendlaendischen Philosophie (Anaximander und Parmenides), 1932 (GA 35).Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Heidegger,Die Selbstbehauptung der deutschen Universitaet (Breslau: Verlag Wilh. Gottl. Korn, 1977), pp. 8–11, trans. James Crooks—working from an unpublished English rendering by Cyril Welch.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Most, p. 97. The run-up to this conclusion—a concise statement of the recipe for Heideggerian classicism—is worthy of note. It binds the skeptical attitude of the discipline directly to the scholarly inheritance I want to represent as necessary (but not sufficient) for grasping the Nietzschean/Heideggerian appropriation of tragedy. Most writes: ‘Heidegger tacitly presupposes a largely German professionalAltertumswissenschaft in his use of editions, commentaries, lexica, and etymological dictionaries; he tacitly presupposes German Philhellenism in his evident belief that he need only assert the world-historical privilege of the ancient Greeks over other cultures without having to explain or defent it in detail; he tacitly presupposes a typically German and specifically Nietzschean nostalgia for origins in his no less evident belief that he need only assert the superiority of the earlier Greeks over the later ones without having to explain or defend that in detail either. In all these regards, Heidegger is an absolutely typical German thinker ….’Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    III, p. 881, trans. Walter Kaufmann inThe Will to Power (New York: Random House, 1967), p. 7.Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    Heidegger, ‘Die seinsgeschichtliche Bestimmung des Nihilismus’ in Id.,Nietzsche II (Pfullingen: Verlag Guenther Neske, 1961), p. 342, trans. by Frank A. Capuzzi as ‘Nihilism as Determined by the History of Being’ inNietzsche, Volume IV:Nihilism (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1984), p. 204.Google Scholar
  16. 16.
    In a recent discussion of Nietzsche and Aristotle (‘Is There Such a Thing as Nietzsche's Aristotle?’ inWhose Aristotle? Whose Aristotelianism?, ed. R.W. Sharples [Aldershot: Ashgate, 2001], pp. 150–68), Monique Dixsaut argues convincingly that Nietzsche objects to the account of tragedy in thePoetics because it reduces its play of forces to human terms. Nevertheless, his philosophical appropriation of ‘tragic knowledge’ in the analysis of nihilism as a crisis of valueat the historical/cultural level is harmonious with Aristotle on at least two important points. In the transfiguration of its suffering into a cosmic desity, as I argue below, thereactive Judeo-Christian culture that reaches the apex of its development in the modern world misjudges the process of value-positing by which it is constituted. Thishamartia, in turn, makes theperipeteia/anagnorisis of nihilism's advent (it's ‘knocking at the door’) inevitable.Google Scholar
  17. 17.
    III, p. 432,The Will to Power, pp. 531–2.Google Scholar
  18. 18.
    Ibid. p. 557, Ibid.The Will to Power, p. 9.Google Scholar
  19. 19.
    Nietzsche II, p. 394–5,Nietzsche, Volume IV:Nihilism, p. 248.Google Scholar
  20. 20.
    II, p. 1152, trans. R.J. Hollingdale asEcce Homo. How one becomes what one is (Middlesex: Penguin Books, 1980), p. 126.Google Scholar
  21. 21.
    Cf.Die Technik und die Kehre (Pfullingen: Neske, 1982), p. 32.Google Scholar
  22. 22.
    Cf. ‘Der Spruch des Anaximander’,Holzwege pp. 296–343.Google Scholar
  23. 23.
    Heidegger,Vortraege und Aufsaetze (GA 7, Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann), pp. 163–4, trans. Albert Hofstadter inPoetry, Language and Thought (New York: Harper & Row, 1971), p. 161.Google Scholar
  24. 24.
    II, p. 115, trans. Thomas Common inJoyful Wisdom (New York: Ungar, 1987), p. 152.Google Scholar
  25. 25.
    Sophocles,Antigone, 332–333, trans. Hugh Lloyd-Jones inSophocles II, ser. Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press, 1994). InEinfuehrung in die Metaphysik, Heidegger translates δɛινά asunheimlich—i.e., strange, unhomely. Cf. esp. pp. 149–56.Google Scholar
  26. 26.
    Cf.Die Technik und die Kehre, pp. 16–46.Google Scholar
  27. 27.
    Heidegger, ‘Der Wille zur Macht als Kunst’ in Id.,Nietzsche I (Pfullingen: Verlag Guenther Neske, 1961), p. 36, trans. David Farrell Krell inNietzsche, Volume I:The Will to Power as Art (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1979), p. 27.Google Scholar
  28. 28.
    Heidegger,Einfuehrung in die Metaphysik, p. 39,An Introduction to Metaphysics, p. 36.Google Scholar
  29. 29.
    Cf. Derrida,Éperons, Les Styles de Nietzsche/Spurs, Nietzsche's Styles, English trans. Barbara Harlow (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1978), p. 108–9.Google Scholar
  30. 30.
    Cf. ‘Hoelderlin und das Wesen der Dichtung’ inErlaeuterungen zu Hoelderlins Dichtung (GA 4, 1981), p. 41.Google Scholar
  31. 31.
    Symposium, 321e, trans. W.R.M. Lamb inPlato III, ser. Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991), p. 239.Google Scholar
  32. 32.
    Cf.Physics, 199a20–25.Google Scholar
  33. 33.
    Physics, 199b29–32, trans. Philip H. Wicksteed and Francis M. Cornford inAristotle I, ser. Loeb Classical Library (London: Harvard University Press, 1957), p. 179.Google Scholar
  34. 34.
    Heidegger,Was heisst Denken? (Tuebingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag, 1961), p. 51, trans. J. Glenn Gray inWhat is Called Thinking? (New York: Harper Colophon Books, 1968), p. 16–7.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer 2002

Authors and Affiliations

  • James Crooks
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyBishops UniversityLennovilleCanada

Personalised recommendations