Advertisement

Forum for Social Economics

, Volume 29, Issue 2, pp 33–48 | Cite as

The Arrow-Debreu model: How math can hide a fatal conceptual error

  • David Ellerman
Symposium On Mathematics in Economics

Abstract

I argue that math, like love, can cover a multitude of sins, and I use the neoclassical object of adoration, the Arrow-Debreu model, as the case in point. It is commonplace that the Arrow-Debreu (AD) model of general equilibrium does not describe the real world, but it is equally commonplace to accept it as representing the pure logic of the competitive capitalist economy in an idealized world free of transactions costs. I show that the AD model fails even as an idealized model; it actually mistakes the logic of pure capitalism. Unlike McKenzie’s model of idealized general equilibrium under constant returns to scale, Arrow and Debreu claim to have shown the existence of competitive equilibrium under decreasing returns to scale and positive pure profits. The AD model (again unlike the McKinzie model) needs to assign the profits to individuals and this is done using the notion of “ownership of the production set.” But this notion suffers from a fatal ambiguity. If Arrow and Debreu interpret it to mean “ownership of a corporation” then a simple argument in the form “labor can hire capital or capital can hire labor” defeats the alleged necessity of assigning residual claimancy to the corporation. A given corporation may or may not end up exploiting a set of production opportunities (represented by a production set) depending on whether it hires in labor and undertakes production or hires out its capital to others (all by assumption at the parametrically given prices). In the latter case, residual claimancy is elsewhere. There is no such property right as “ownership of a production set” in a private property market economy. The legal party which purchases or already owns all the inputs used up in production has the defensible legal claim on the outputs: there is no need to also “purchase the production set.” At any set of prices that allow positive pure profits, anyone in the idealized AD model could bid up the price of the inputs and thus try to reap a smaller but still positive profit. Therefore,pace Arrow and Debreu, there could be no equilibrium with positive pure profits. In the Appendix, the property rights fallacy that afflicts the AD model is shown to also afflict orthodox capital theory and corporate finance theory.

Keywords

Capital Good Social Economic Competitive Equilibrium Capital Asset Asset Owner 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Arrow, K.J. (1971). “The Firm in General Equilibrium Theory.” R. Marris and A. Woods, eds.The Corporate Economy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  2. — and Debreu, G. (1954). “Existence of an Equilibrium for a Competitive Economy.”Econometrica. 22: 265–290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. — and Hahn, F.H. (1971).General Competitive Analysis. San Francisco: Holden-Day.Google Scholar
  4. Burmeister, E. (1974). “Neo-Austrian and Alternative Approaches to Capital Theory,”Journal of Economic Literature. XII: 413–456.Google Scholar
  5. Ellerman, David P. (1982).Economics, Accounting, and Property Theory. Lexington MA: D.C. Heath.Google Scholar
  6. — (1992).Property & Contract in Economics: The Case for Economic Democracy. Cambridge USA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  7. — (1995).Intellectual Trespassing as a Way of Life: Essays in Philosophy, Economics, and Mathematics. Lanham MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  8. Hahn, Frank. (December 1988). “Review of Nicholas Kaldor by Anthony Thirlwall.”Journal of Economic Literature. XXVI: 1746–1747.Google Scholar
  9. Keynes, J.M. (1936).The General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.Google Scholar
  10. Koopmans, T.C. (1957).Three Essays on The State of Economic Science. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
  11. McKenzie, L. (April 1954). “On Equilibrium in Graham’s Model of World Trade and Other Competitive Systems,”Econometrica. 22: 147–161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. — (1959). “On the Existence of a General Equilibrium in a Competitive Market,”Econometrica. 27: 54–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. — (1981). “The Classical Theorem on Existence of Competitive Equilibrium,”Econometrica. 49, 4: 819–841.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Miller, M. H. and F. Modigliani. (October 1961). “Dividend Policy, Growth, and the Valuation of Shares.”The Journal of Business. 34: 411–433.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Montias, J. M. (1976).The Structure of Economic Systems. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Putterman, L. (1996). “Ownership and the nature of the firm.” L. Putterman and R. Krozner, eds.The Economic Nature of the Firm. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press: 361–369.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer 2000

Authors and Affiliations

  • David Ellerman

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations