Biological Theory

, Volume 13, Issue 2, pp 76–92 | Cite as

Life as Adaptive Capacity: Bringing New Life to an Old Debate

Thematic Issue Article: Astrobiology

Abstract

Whatever we take “life” to mean, it must involve an attempt to describe the objective reality beyond scientists’ biases. Traditionally, this is thought to involve comparing our scientific categories to “natural kinds.” But this approach has been tainted with an implicit metaphysics, inherited from Aristotle, that does not fit biological reality. In particular, we must accept that biological categories will never be specifiable in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions or shared underlying physical structures that produce clean boundaries. Biology blurs all lines and failure to embrace this unique feature has blocked attempts to reach consensus on the meaning of “life.” Thus, while the three classical accounts (thermodynamic, metabolic, and evolutionary) all fall short of offering a complete definition, their advocates fail to realize that they share the same view of life’s ultimate, functional hallmark: its uniquely rich adaptive capacity. I develop an account of life as adaptive capacity that sidesteps debates about the relative importance of specific mechanisms and the precise location of boundaries to bring the three classical accounts together under a shared conceptual framework.

Keywords

Adaptation Aristotle Complexity Definition Life Natural kind 

Notes

Acknowledgements

The ideas in this article were inspired by numerous conversations with too many colleagues to mention. However, extensive comments provided on an earlier draft by Carlos Mariscal and Erik Persson were especially helpful. Any deficiencies that remain are, of course, entirely the fault of the author.

References

  1. Adami C (2002) What is complexity? BioEssays 24:1085–1094CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Baross J (2007) The limits of organic life in planetary systems. National Academies Press, Washington DCGoogle Scholar
  3. Beatty J (1995) The evolutionary contingency thesis. In: Wolters G, Lennox J (eds) Concepts, theories and rationality in the biological sciences. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, pp 45–81Google Scholar
  4. Bedau M (1996) The nature of life. In: Boden M (ed) The philosophy of artificial life. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 332–357Google Scholar
  5. Boyd R (1991) Realism, anti-foundationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philos Stud 61(1/2):127–148CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Brandon R (1990) Adaptation and environment. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  7. Brandon R, Antonovics J, Burian R et al (1994) Sober on Brandon on screening-off and the levels of selection. Philos Sci 61(3):475–486CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Cavazzoni C, Chiarotti GL, Scandolo S et al (1999) Superionic and metallic states of water and ammonia at giant planet conditions. Science 283(5398):44–46CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Chaisson E (2002) Cosmic evolution: the rise of complexity in nature. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  10. Chyba C, Mcdonald GD (1995) Annu Rev Earth Planet Sci 23:15–249CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Ćirković M, Bradbury R (2006) Galactic gradients, postbiological evolution and the apparent failure of SETI. New Astron 11(8):628–639CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Cleland C (2012) Life without definitions. Synthese 185:125–144CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Cleland C, Chyba C (2002) Defining "life." Orig Life Evol Bios 32:387–393CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Cleland C, Chyba C (2007) Does "life" have a definition? In: Sullivan W, Baross JA (eds) Planets and life: the emerging science of astrobiology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 119–131Google Scholar
  15. Cleland C, Copley S (2005) The possibility of alternative microbial life on earth. Int J Astrobiol 4:165–173CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Cleland C, Zerella M (2013) What is life? In: Kampourakis K (ed) The philosophy of biology. Springer, New York, pp 31–48CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Davies P (2011) The Eerie silence. Mariner Books, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  18. Donoghue M (1985) A critique of the biological species concept and recommendations for a phylogenetic alternative. Bryologist 88(3):172–181CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Ereshefsky M (2009) Natural kinds in biology. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Taylor and Francis, https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/natural-kinds-in-biology/v-1. Accessed 1 Sept 17
  20. Fleischaker G (1990) Origins of life: an operational definition. Org Life Evol Biosph 20(2):127–137CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Gould S (1989) Wonderful life. New York, NortonGoogle Scholar
  22. Joyce G, Deamer D, Fleischaker G (1994) Origins of life: the central concepts. Jones and Bartlett, BostonGoogle Scholar
  23. Korzeniewski B (2005) Confrontation of the cybernetic definition of living individual with the real world. Acta Biotheor 53:1–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Koshland D (2002) The seven pillars of life. Science 295:2215–2216CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Lauder G, Tytell E (2006) Hydrodynamics of undulatory propulsion. In: Shadwick R, Lauder G (eds) Fish biomechanics. Fish Physiology, vol 23. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 425–468.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Machery E (2011) Why I stopped worrying about the definition of life…and why you should as well. Synthese 185(1):145–164CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Mackie J (1965) Causes and conditions. Am Philos Q 12:245–265Google Scholar
  28. Margulis L, Sagan D (1995) What is life? Simon and Schuster, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  29. Mariscal C (2016) Universal biology: assessing universality from a single example. In: Dick S (ed) The impact of discovering life beyond earth. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 113–126Google Scholar
  30. Mayr E (2000) The biological species concept. In: Wheeler Q, Meier R (eds) Species concepts and phylogenetic history. Columbia University Press, New York, pp 17–29Google Scholar
  31. McKay C (1998) Life in the planetary context. In: Woodward C, Shull M, Thronson H (eds) Origins, ASP conference series, vol 148, pp 449–456Google Scholar
  32. Milligan T (2015) Nobody owns the moon. McFarland Publishing, JeffersonGoogle Scholar
  33. Mishler B, Brandon R (1987) Individuality, pluralism, and the phylogenetic species concept. Biol Philos 2(4):397–414CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Nixon K, Wheeler Q (1990) An amplification of the phylogenetic species concept. Cladistics 6(3):211–223CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Oliver J, Perry R (2006) Definitely life but not definitively. Orig Life Evol Bios 36:515–521CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Olson E (1997) The ontological basis of strong artificial life. Artif Life 3(1):29–39CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Persson E (2013) Philosophical aspects of astrobiology. In: Dunér D, Pathermore J, Persson E, Holmberg G (eds) The history and philosophy of astrobiology. Cambridge Scholars Press, Newcastle upon Tyne, pp 29–48Google Scholar
  38. Popa R (2004) Between necessity and probability. Springer, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  39. Prigogine I (1973) Can thermodynamics explain biological order. Impact Sci Soc 23(3):159–169Google Scholar
  40. Putnam H (1973) Meaning and reference. J Philos 70:699–711CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Reichenbach H (1956) The direction of time. University of Los Angeles Press, BerkeleyGoogle Scholar
  42. Rieppel O (2009) Species monophyly. J Zoolog Syst Evolut Res 48(1):1–8Google Scholar
  43. Schneider E, Sagan D (2005) Into the cool—energy flow, thermodynamics, and life. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  44. Schrödinger E (1944) What is life—the physical aspect of the living cell. Cambridge University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  45. Smith KC (1993) Marketing structuralism: reflections on the process structuralist critique of neo-darwinism. Rivista di Biologia/Biol Forum 86(3–4):578–579Google Scholar
  46. Smith KC (2014) Manifest complexity: a foundational ethics for astrobiology? Space Policy 30(4):209–214CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Smith KC (2016) Life is hard: countering definitional pessimism concerning the definition of life. Int J Astrobiol 15(4):277–289CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Szostak J (2012) Attempts to define life do not help to understand the origin of life. J Biomol Struc Dynam 29(4):599–600CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Toepfer G (2012) Teleology and its constitutive role for biology as the science of organized systems in nature. Stud Hist Philos Sci 43(1):113–119Google Scholar
  50. Trifonov E (2012) Definition of life: navigation through uncertainties. J Biomol Struc Dynam 29(4):647–650CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Wagner A (2013) Robustness and evolvability in living systems. Princeton University Press, PrincetonCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Walker S, Davies P (2013) The algorithmic origins of life. J R Soc Interface.  https://doi.org/10.1098/rsif.2012.0869 Google Scholar
  53. Weaver W (1948) Science and complexity. Am Sci 36:536–544Google Scholar
  54. Zyga L (2016) Did the 40-year-old Viking experiment discover life on Mars? Phys.org, https://phys.org/news/2016-10-year-old-viking-life-mars.html. Accessed 30 Aug 2017

Copyright information

© Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Philosophy and ReligionClemson UniversityClemsonUSA

Personalised recommendations