Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Idealism, Realism, and Success in Armed Humanitarian Intervention

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

An armed humanitarian intervention (AHI) must have a reasonable prospect of success to be justified. It must also be a proportional last resort. These are necessary conditions for legitimate AHI. It has been suggested that, in addition to these necessary conditions, there are also ideal conditions of AHI, namely disinterest and multilateralism. These conditions are said to enhance the moral credentials of an armed intervention without being strictly required. The paper concerns itself with the relationship between these two ideals and the requirement of a reasonable prospect of success. Specifically, I explore the suggestion that the former are in some way instrumental to the latter. On this view, we should aspire towards disinterest and multilateralism because these things contribute to a positive humanitarian outcome. If this is correct then the ideal conditions can be partly grounded in, or justified in reference to, the prospect of success principle.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Responsibility to Protect, Report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty, Ottawa: International Development Research Centre, 2001, at http://responsibilitytoprotect.org/ICISS%20Report.pdf, last accessed 29/09/2014. Some of the material in this paper is taken from work previously published. See especially Ned Dobos 2008, 2010a; Dobos 2012.

  2. Some commentators are at pains to stress that they are not advancing this consequence-based argument. Uwe-Jens Heuer and Gregor Schirmer (1998) write: “We do not want to deny that military interventions like those of the Soviet Union in Afghanistan, or Vietnam in Pol Pot’s Cambodia, or of the United States in Somalia may well have saved human lives, and may well have worked to the benefit of those threatened by hunger and terror. But in all these cases, and in others as well, the altruism of the intervening parties was a mere secondary phenomenon to crude self-interested efforts towards the expansion of political and military power, spheres of economic influence, and the like.

  3. See also Luttwak 1995.

  4. Hence it was not until Vietnam that the “body-bag effect” really kicked it. During the two World Wars and the Korean War, conscription ensured that the costs were shared by all sectors of American society, whereas in Vietnam many of the privileged managed to escape the draft by living abroad or extending university studies. Moreover blacks remained over-represented on the casualties list. Since fewer of them had formal education, they were assigned disproportionately to the combat-intensive infantry (See Moskos 2002).

  5. Richard Falk (1993: p. 760) writes that “the higher value attached to the lives of the intervening side… led to a callous disregard for the lives of the indigenous people, especially civilians”, who were killed indiscriminately by American forces. The battle that killed 18 US Rangers claimed the lives of several hundred Somalis; a statistic that history forgot.

  6. I have addressed this issue elsewhere (See Dobos 2010b).

References

  • Amos. (1880). Political and Legal Remedies for War. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2001). A review of NATO’s War Over Kosovo. USA: Z-Magazine

  • Coates, A. (2006). Humanitarian intervention: A conflict of traditions. In T. Nardin & M. S. Williams (Eds.), NOMOS XLVII: Humanitarian intervention. New York and London: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coghlan, P. (2003). War and liberation. In R. Gaita (Ed.), Why the war was wrong. Melbourne: Text Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corten, O. (1999). Humanitarian intervention: a controversial right. UNESCO Courier, 52(7).

  • Dobos, N. (2008). Rebellion, humanitarian intervention, and the prudential constraints on war. Journal of Military Ethics, 7(2), 102–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobos, N. (2010a). Is U.N. Security Council authorisation for armed humanitarian intervention morally necessary? Philosophia, 38(3), 499–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobos, N. (2010b). On Altruistic War and National Responsibility: Justifying Humanitarian Intervention to Soldiers and Taxpayers. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 13(1), 19–31.

  • Dobos, N. (2012). Insurrection and intervention: The two faces of sovereignty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durch, W. J. (1997). Introduction to anarchy: Humanitarian intervention and ‘State Building’ in Somalia. In W. J. Durch (Ed.), UN peacekeeping, American policy, and the uncivil wars of the 1990s. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Falk, R. (1993). Intervention revisited: Hard choices and tragic dilemmas. The Nation, Michigan: Gale Group, Farmington Hills.

  • Frowe, H. (2014). Judging armed humanitarian intervention. In D. E. Scheid (Ed.), The ethics of armed humanitarian intervention. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heinze, E. A. (2004). The moral limits of humanitarian intervention: reconciling human respect and utility. Polity, 36(4), 543–558.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heinze, E. (2009). Waging humanitarian war: The ethics, Law, and politics of humanitarian intervention. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heuer, U-J, & Schirmer, G. (1998). Human rights imperialism. Monthly Review, 49(10).

  • Kardas, S. (2003). Humanitarian intervention: a conceptual analysis. Alternatives: Turkish Journal of International Relations, 2(3–4), 21–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luban, D. (2002). Intervention and civilization: Some unhappy lessons of the Kosovo war. In P. de Greiff & C. Cronin (Eds.), Global justice and transnational politics: Essays on the moral and political challenges of globalization. Cambridge Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luttwak, E. N. (1995). Towards post-heroic warfare. Foreign Affairs, 74(3)

  • Luttwak, E. (1999). Give war a chance. Foreign Affairs, 78(4), 36–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luttwak, E. (2009). The virtual American empire: War, faith, and power. New Brunswick NJ: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, M. (1999a). A perfect failure: NATO’s war against Yugoslavia. Foreign Affairs, 78(5), 3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, M. (1999b). Learning to be warless. Survival, 41(2).

  • Mistiaen, V. (2004). Offering dignity to Rwanda Genocide victims: Survivor confronts the horror to honor the dead and living San Fransisco Chronicle. Friday, April 9, 2004.

  • Morgenthau, H. J. (1951). In defense of the national interest: A critical examination of American foreign policy. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moskos, C. C. (2002). Our will to fight depends on who is willing to die. Wall Street Journal, p A22.

  • Peterson, P. G. (1999). Gray dawn: the global ageing crisis. Foreign Affairs, 78(1).

  • Seybolt, T. (2007). Humanitarian military intervention: The conditions for success and failure. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, H. (2005). What costs will democracies bear? A review of popular theories of casualty aversion. Armed Forces and Society, 31(4), 501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Telhami, T. (2004). Double Blow to Mideast Democracy. Washington: Washington Post

  • Verwey, W. (1998). Humanitarian intervention in the 1990s and beyond: An international law perspective. In J. N. Pieterse (Ed.), World orders in the making. London: Macmillan Press Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, M. (1980). The moral standing of states: a response to four critics. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 9(3), 209–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, E. M. (2000). Kosovo and the new imperialism. In T. Ali (Ed.), Masters of the universe? NATO’s Balkan crusade. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ned Dobos.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dobos, N. Idealism, Realism, and Success in Armed Humanitarian Intervention. Philosophia 44, 497–507 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9704-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9704-0

Keywords

Navigation