Abstract
Counterpossibles are counterfactuals that involve some metaphysical impossibility. Modal normativism is a non-descriptivist account of metaphysical necessity and possibility according to which modal claims, e.g. ‘necessarily, all bachelors are unmarried’, do not function as descriptive claims about the modal nature of reality but function as normative illustrations of constitutive rules and permissions that govern the use of ordinary non-modal vocabulary, e.g. ‘bachelor’. In this paper, I assume modal normativism and develop a novel account of counterpossibles and claims about metaphysical similarity between possible and impossible worlds. I argue that considerations of metaphysical similarity between various impossible worlds and the actual world only require us to tacitly consider how the actual constitutive rules that govern the use of our terms change in order to accommodate the description of some hypothetical impossible scenario. I then argue for my account by raising worries for alternative epistemic and realist accounts of counterpossibles and showing how my account avoids those worries.
Keywords
Counterpossibles Impossible worlds Modality Modal normativism Conceptual analysis Metaphysical lawsNotes
Acknowledgements
I am especially grateful to Amie Thomasson for extensive comments on multiple drafts of this paper. Many thanks to Otávio Bueno, Berit Brogaard, Eli Chudnoff, and Daniel Nolan for helpful comments and suggestions. Thanks to audiences at the University of Miami Philosophy Forum and the Rutgers University 2016 Metaphysical Mayhem for helpful discussion on earlier drafts of this paper. Finally, thanks to two anonymous reviewers for great feedback and suggestions.
References
- Bernstein, S. (2016). Omission impossible. Philosophical Studies, 173, 2575–2589.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Berto, F., French, R., Priest, G., & Priest, D. (2017). Williamson on counterpossibles. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 47, 693–713.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Blackburn, S. (1993). Morals and modals. Essays in quasi-realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Braddon-Mitchell, D. (2009). Naturalistic analysis and the a priori. In R. Nola & D. Braddon-Mitchell (Eds.), Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism, Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 23–44.Google Scholar
- Brandom, R. (2000). Articulating reasons: An introduction to inferentialism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Brandom, R. (2008). Between saying and doing: Towards an analytic pragmatism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Brandom, R. (2014). Modal expressivism and modal realism: Together again. (Unpublished) http://www.pitt.edu/~brandom/currentwork.html. Accessed 20 Aug 2016.
- Brogaard, B., & Salerno, J. (2013). Remarks on counterpossibles. Synthese, 190, 639–660.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Einheuser, I. (2006). Counterconventional conditionals. Philosophical Studies, 127(3), 459–482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Horwich, P. (1999). Truth (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Jago, M. (2014). The Impossible: An essay on hyperintensionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Jenkins, C. S., & Nolan, D. (2012). Disposition impossible. Noûs, 46(4), 732–753.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Jenny, M. (2018). Counterpossibles in science: The case of relative computability. Noûs, 52(3), 530–560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kim, S., & Maslen, C. (2006). Counterfactuals as short stories. Philosophical Studies, 129(1), 81–117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kment, B. (2006). Counterfactuals and the analysis of necessity. Philosophical Perspectives, 20, 237–302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kment, B. (2014). Modality and explanatory reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Krakauer, B. (2012). Counterpossibles. Open Access Dissertations. 522. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/open_access_dissertations/522. Accessed 20 Aug 2016.
- Lewis, D. K. (1973). Counterfactuals. New York: Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Lewis, D. K. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Nolan, D. (1997). Impossible worlds: A modest approach. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 38, 535–573.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Nolan, D. (2014). Hyperintensional metaphysics. Philosophical Studies, 171(1), 149–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Plunkett, D. (2015). Which concepts should we use? Metalinguistic negotiations and the methodology of philosophy. Inquiry, 58(7-8), 828–874.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Raven, M. J. (2012). In defense of ground. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90(4), 687–701.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Rayo, A. (2015). Essence without fundamentality. Theoria, 30, 349–363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Ryle, G. (2000). The concept of mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
- Schiffer, S. (2003). The things we mean. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Sellars, W. (1958). Counterfactuals, dispositions and the causal modalities. In H. Feigl, M. Scriven, & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Minnesota studies in philosophy of science Volume 2: Concepts, theories and the mind-body problem (pp. 225–308). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
- Sidelle, A. (1989). Necessity, essence, and individuation: A defense of conventionalism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
- Sider, T. (2011). Writing the book of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In R. Nicholas (Ed.), Studies in logical theory (American Philosophical Quarterly Monographs 2) (pp. 98–112). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Steinberg, A. (2013). Pleonastic possible worlds. Philosophical Studies, 164, 767–789.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Thomasson, A. (2007a). Ordinary objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Thomasson, A. (2007b). Modal normativism and the methods of metaphysics. Philosophical Topics, 35(1/2), 135–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Thomasson, A. (2009). Non-descriptivism about modality: A brief history and revival. In Baltic international yearbook of cognition, logic and communication (Vol 4, pp. 1–26). New Prairie Press.Google Scholar
- Thomasson, A. (2013). 2012 Nancy D. Simco lecture: Norms and necessity. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 51(2), 143–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Thomasson, A. (2015). Ontology made easy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Thomasson, A. (2017). Metaphysical disputes and metalinguistic negotiations. Analytic Philosophy, 58(1), 1–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Vander Laan, D. (2007). Counterpossibles and similarity. In F. Jackson & G. Priest (Eds.), Lewisian themes: The philosophy of David K Lewis (pp. 258–276). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Vetter, B. (2016). Counterpossibles (not only) for dispositionalists. Philosophical Studies, 173, 2681–2700.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Warren, J. (2014). Conventionalism, consistency, and consistency sentences. Synthese, 192(5), 1351–1371.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Warren, J. (2015a). Talking with tonkers. Philosophers Imprint, 15(24), 1–24.Google Scholar
- Warren, J. (2015b). The possibility of truth by convention. Philosophical Quarterly, 65(258), 84–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Warren, J. (2017). Epistemology versus non-causal realism. Synthese, 194, 1643–1662.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Williamson, T. (2016). Counterpossibles. Topoi, 37(3), 1–12.Google Scholar
- Williamson, T. (2017). Counterpossibles in metaphysics. In B. Armour-Garb & F. Kroon (Eds.), Philosophical fictionalism (forthcoming).Google Scholar
- Wilson, A. (2016). Grounding entails counterpossible non-triviality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12305.Google Scholar