Advertisement

Synthese

pp 1–20 | Cite as

Moral disagreement and non-moral ignorance

  • Nicholas SmythEmail author
Article

Abstract

The existence of deep and persistent moral disagreement poses a problem for a defender of moral knowledge. It seems particularly clear that a philosopher who thinks that we know a great many moral truths should explain how human populations have failed to converge on those truths. In this paper, I do two things. First, I show that the problem is more difficult than it is often taken to be, and second, I criticize a popular response, which involves claiming that many false moral beliefs are the product of nonmoral ignorance.

Keywords

Moral disagreement Meta-ethics Moral psychology 

Notes

Acknowledgements

The author wishes to thank Robert Joynt, Miquel Miralbes del Pino, and Iain Laidley for a great deal of very valuable discussion.

References

  1. Audi, R. (2008). Rational disagreement as a challenge to practical ethics and moral theory: An essay in moral epistemology. In Q. Smith (Ed.), Epistemology: New essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Boyd, R. (1988). How to be a moral realist. In G. Sayre-McCord (Ed.), Essays on moral realism (pp. 181–228). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Bloomfield, P. (2008). Disagreement about disagreement. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology, Vol. 2. The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity (pp. 303–331). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  4. Brink, D. (1984). Moral realism and the sceptical arguments from disagreement and queerness. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 62(2), 111–125.Google Scholar
  5. Brink, D. (1989). Moral realism and the foundations of ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Brown, M. L. (1992). Our hands are stained with blood. Shippensburg: Destiny Image Publishers.Google Scholar
  7. Daniels, N. (1979). Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics. Journal of Philosophy, 76(5), 256–282.Google Scholar
  8. Doris, J. M. (2015). Talking to our selves: Reflection, ignorance, and agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Doris, J. M., & Plakias, A. (2008). How to argue about disagreement: Evaluative diversity and moral realism. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology, Vol. 2. The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity (pp. 303–331). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  10. Ellsworth, P. C., & Gross, S. R. (1994). Hardening of the attitudes: Americans’ views on the death penalty. Journal of Social Issues, 50(2), 19–52.Google Scholar
  11. Enoch, D. (2009). How is moral disagreement a problem for realism? Journal of Ethics, 13(1), 15–50.Google Scholar
  12. Enoch, D. (2010). Not just a truthometer: Taking oneself seriously (but not too seriously) in cases of peer disagreement. Mind, 119(476), 953–997.Google Scholar
  13. Enoch, D. (2011). Taking morality seriously: A defense of robust realism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Firth, R. (1952). Ethical absolutism and the ideal observer. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 12(3), 317–345.Google Scholar
  15. Fitzpatrick, S. (2014). Moral realism, moral disagreement, and moral psychology. Philosophical Papers, 43(2), 161–190.Google Scholar
  16. Foucault, M. (1977). Discipline and punish: The birth of the prison. New York: Vintage.Google Scholar
  17. Gewirth, A. (1994). Is cultural pluralism relevant to moral knowledge? Social Philosophy and Policy, 11(1), 22–43.Google Scholar
  18. Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108(4), 814.Google Scholar
  19. Haidt, J., & Bjorklund, F. (2008). Social intuitionists answer six questions about morality. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology (Vol. 2). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  20. Harman, G. (1975). Moral relativism defended. Philosophical Review, 84(1), 3–22.Google Scholar
  21. Jones, K. (2005). Moral epistemology. In F. Jackson & M. Smith (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of contemporary philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  23. Kelly, T. (2005). The epistemic significance of disagreement (Vol. 1, pp. 167–196)., Oxford studies in epistemology Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Kelly, D., Faucher, L., & Machery, E. (2010). Getting rid of racism: Assessing three proposals in light of psychological evidence. Journal of Social Philosophy, 41(3), 293–322.Google Scholar
  25. Kennett, J., & Fine, C. (2009). Will the real moral judgment please stand up? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 12(1), 77–96.Google Scholar
  26. Knobe, J. (2010). Person as scientist, person as moralist. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(4), 315.Google Scholar
  27. Kruglanski, A. W. (1996). Motivated social cognition: Principles of the interface. In E. T. Higgins & A. W. Kruglanski (Eds.), Social psychology: Handbook of basic principles. New York: Guilford Press.Google Scholar
  28. Kunda, Z. (1990). The case for motivated reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 108(3), 480.Google Scholar
  29. Kundra, Z., & Sinclair, L. (1999). Motivated reasoning with stereotypes: Activation, application, and inhibition. Psychological Inquiry, 10(1), 12–22.Google Scholar
  30. Lambert, E. G., Clarke, A., & Lambert, J. (2004). Reasons for supporting and opposing capital punishment in the USA, Toronto. Internet Journal of Criminology, 1, 1–34.Google Scholar
  31. Lenman, J. (2000). Consequentialism and cluelessness. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 29(4), 342–370.Google Scholar
  32. Loeb, D. (1998). Moral realism and the argument from disagreement. Philosophical Studies, 90(3), 281–303.Google Scholar
  33. Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. Baltimore: Penguin.Google Scholar
  34. McGrath, S. (2007). Moral disagreement and moral expertise. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 4, pp. 87–108). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  35. Moody-Adams, M. M. (1997). Fieldwork in familiar places: Morality, culture, and philosophy. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Murray, S. L. (1999). The quest for conviction: Motivated cognition in romantic relationships. Psychological Inquiry, 10(1), 23–34.Google Scholar
  37. Nietzsche, F. W. (1886/1990). Beyond good and evil: prelude to a philosophy of the future. Baltimore: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  38. Parfit, D. (2011). On What Matters. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  39. Plunkett, D., & Sundell, T. (2013). Disagreement and the semantics of normative and evaluative terms. Philosophers’ Imprint, 13(23), 1–37.Google Scholar
  40. Pritchard, D. (2008). Sensitivity, safety, and anti-luck epistemology. In J. Greco (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of skepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  41. Ratchnevsky, P. (1993). Genghis Khan: His life and legacy. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
  42. Sauer, H. (2012). Educated intuitions. Automaticity and rationality in moral judgement. Philosophical Explorations, 15(3), 255–275.Google Scholar
  43. Sayre-McCord, G. (1996). Coherentist epistemology and moral theory. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong & M. Timmons (Eds.), Moral Knowledge? New Readings in Moral Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  44. Scanlon, T. M. (2014). Being realistic about reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Setiya, K. (2012). Knowing right from wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  46. Shafer-Landau, R. (1994). Ethical disagreement, ethical objectivism and moral indeterminacy. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54(2), 331–344.Google Scholar
  47. Shafer-Landau, R. (2003). Moral realism: A defence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  48. Smith, D. L. (2014). Dehumanization, essentialism, and moral psychology. Philosophy Compass, 9(11), 814–824.Google Scholar
  49. Smyth, N. (2017). Moral knowledge and the genealogy of error. Journal of Value Inquiry, 51(3), 455–474.Google Scholar
  50. Sripada, C., & Stich, S. (2006). A framework for the psychology of norms. In P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. P. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind, volume 2: Culture and cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  51. Street, S. (2009). In defense of future Tuesday indifference: Ideally coherent eccentrics and the contingency of what matters. Philosophical Issues, 19(1), 273–298.Google Scholar
  52. Vavova, K. (2014). Moral disagreement and moral skepticism. Philosophical Perspectives, 28(1), 302–333.Google Scholar
  53. Weatherson, B. (2010). Do judgments screen evidence? (unpublished manuscript).Google Scholar
  54. Wedgwood, R. (2010). The moral evil demons. In R. Feldman & T. Warfield (Eds.), Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  55. Wedgwood, R. (2014). Moral disagreement among philosophers. In M. Bergmann & P. Kain (Eds.), Challenges to moral and religious belief: Disagreement and evolution (pp. 23–39). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  56. Williams, B. (2009). The point of view of the universe: Sidgwick and the ambitions of ethics. In M. Burnyeat (Ed.), The sense of the past: Essays in the history of philosophy (pp. 277–296). Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Fordham UniversityBronxUSA

Personalised recommendations