Advertisement

Synthese

pp 1–25 | Cite as

On the non-conceptual content of affective-evaluative experience

Article
  • 36 Downloads

Abstract

Arguments for attributing non-conceptual content to experience have predominantly been motivated by aspects of the visual perception of empirical properties. In this article, I pursue a different strategy, arguing that a specific class of affective-evaluative experiences have non-conceptual content. The examples drawn on are affective-evaluative experiences of first exposure, in which the subject has a felt valenced intentional attitude towards evaluative properties of the object of their experience, but lacks any powers of conceptual discrimination regarding those evaluative properties. I also show that by accepting this thesis we can explain relevant features of evaluative understanding.

Keywords

Non-conceptual Content Affective Evaluative Conceptual 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I am thankful to Peter Poellner, Hemdat Lerman, two anonymous reviewers from Synthese, and to audiences at University of Bath, University of Liege, and University of Warwick, for their constructive criticism and comments on previous versions of the paper.

References

  1. Bermudez, J. L. (1994). Peacocke’s argument against the autonomy of nonconceptual content. Mind and Language, 9, 402–418.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bermudez, J. L. (1995). Nonconceptual content: From perceptual experience to subpersonal computational states. Mind and Language, 10, 333–369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bermudez, J. L. (2007). What is at stake in the debate about nonconceptual content? Philosophical Perspectives, 21(1), 55–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Blackburn, S. (1985). Errors and the phenomenology of value. In T. Honderich (Ed.), Morality and objectivity. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  5. Brady, M. (2011). Emotions, perceptions and reasons. In C. Bagnoli (Ed.), Morality and the emotions (pp. 135–149). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Brewer, B. (1999). Perception and reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Burke, E. (2015). A philosophical enquiry into the origin of our ideas of the sublime and the beautiful. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Campbell, J. (2005). Information processing, phenomenal consciousness, and Molyneux’s question. In J. L. Bermudez (Ed.), Thought, reference and experience. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  9. Coliva, A. (2003). The argument from the finer grained content of colour experiences: A redefinition of its role within the debate between McDowell and non-conceptual theorists. Dialectica, 57(1), 57–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Crane, T. (1988). The waterfall illusion. Analysis, 48, 142–147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Crane, T. (1998). Intentionality as the Mark of the Mental. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Contemporary issues in the philosophy of mind (pp. 229–251). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Cussins, A. (1990). The connectionist construction of concepts. In M. Boden (Ed.), The philosophy of artificial intelligence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Deonna, J., & Cova, F. (2014). Being moved. Philosophical Studies, 3, 447–466.Google Scholar
  14. Deonna, J., & Teroni, F. (2012). An introduction to the philosophy of the emotions. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  15. Döring, S. (2007) Seeing What to Do: Affective Perception and Rational Motivation. dialectica, 363–394.Google Scholar
  16. Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  17. Goldie, P. (2000). The emotions: A philosophical exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Gunther, Y. (2003). Emotion and force. In Y. Gunther (Ed.), Essays on nonconceptual content (pp. 279–288). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  19. Heck, R. G. (2000). Nonconceptual content and the space of reasons. Philosophical Review, 109, 483–523.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Husserl, E. (1973) Experience and Judgement (J. S. Churchill, & K. Ameriks, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Johnston, M. (2001). The authority of affect. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63, 181–214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Kant, I. (1998) The Critique of Pure Reason (P. Guyer, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Kant, I. (2011) Observations in the Feeling of the Beautiful and the Sublime and Other Writings (P. Frierson, & P. Guyer, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Kelly, S. D. (2001a). Demonstrative concepts and experience. The Philosophical Review, 110(3), 397–420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Kelly, S. D. (2001b). The non-conceptual content of perceptual experience: situation dependence and fineness of grain. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(3), 601–608.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Lerman, H. (2010). Non-conceptual experiential content and reason-giving. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81(1), 1–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Luntley, M. (2003). Nonconceptual content and the sound of music. Mind and Language, 18(4), 402–426.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Lyons, W. (1980). Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Martin, M. F. M. (1992). Perception, concepts and memory. Philosophical Review, 101(4), 745–763.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. McDowell, J. (1985). Values and secondary qualities. In J. Rachels (Ed.), Ethical theory 1 (pp. 210–226). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  31. McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  32. McDowell, J. (2009). Having the world in view: Essays on Kant, Hegel and Sellars. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  33. McDowell, J. (2013). Perceptual experience: Both relational and contentful. European Journal of Philosophy, 21(1), 144–157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Mendelovici, A. (2014). Pure Intentionalism about moods and emotions. In U. Kriegel (Ed.), Current controversies in philosophy of mind (pp. 135–157). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  35. Mitchell, J. (2017). The epistemology of emotional experience. Dialectica, 71(1), 57–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Montague, M. (2009). The logic, intentionality, and phenomenology of emotion. Philosophical Studies, 145(2), 171–192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Nussbaum, C. N. (2001). Upheavals of thought: The intelligence of emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Peacocke, C. (1992). A study of concepts. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  39. Peacocke, C. (2001). Does perception have a nonconceptual content? Journal of Philosophy, 98, 239–264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Poellner, P. (2003). Non-conceptual content, experience and the self. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(2), 32–57.Google Scholar
  41. Poellner, P. (2016). Phenomenology and the perceptual model of the emotions. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, CXVI(3), 1–28.Google Scholar
  42. Raftopoulous, A., & Muller, V. C. (2006). The phenomenal content of experience. Mind and Language, 21(2), 187–219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Roskies, A. (2008). A new argument for nonconceptual content. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76(3), 633–659.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Sedivy, S. (1996). Must conceptually informed perceptual experience involve non-conceptual content? Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26(3), 413–431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Sellars, W. (1997). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  46. Soteriou, M. (2000). The particularity of visual perception. European Journal of Philosophy, 8(2), 173–189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Stich, S. (1978). Beliefs and subdoxastic state. Philosophy of Science, 45, 499–518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Tappolet, C. (2016). Emotions, values, and agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Teroni, F. (2007). Emotions and formal objects. Dialectica, 61(3), 395–415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Tye, M. (2008). The experience of emotion: An intentionalist theory. Revue Interntionale de philsophie, 243, 25–50.Google Scholar
  51. Wringe, B. (2015). The contents of perception and the contents of emotions. Nous, 49(2), 275–297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of WarwickCoventryUK
  2. 2.KenilworthUK

Personalised recommendations