Advertisement

Synthese

pp 1–15 | Cite as

Life and life only: a radical alternative to life definitionism

  • Carlos Mariscal
  • W. Ford Doolittle
Article

Abstract

To date, no definition of life has been unequivocally accepted by the scientific community. In frustration, some authors advocate alternatives to standard definitions. These include using a list of characteristic features, focusing on life’s effects, or categorizing biospheres rather than life itself; treating life as a fuzzy category, a process or a cluster of contingent properties; or advocating a ‘wait-and-see’ approach until other examples of life are created or discovered. But these skeptical, operational, and pluralistic approaches have intensified the debate, rather than settled it. Given the failure of even these approaches, we advocate a new strategy. In this paper, we reverse the usual line of reasoning and argue that the “life problem” arises from thinking incorrectly about the nature of life. Scientists most often conceptualize life as a class or kind, with earthly life as a single instance of it. Instead, we advocate thinking about Earth’s Life (with a capital ‘L’) as an individual, in the way that species are now thought to be. In this view, Life is a monophyletic clade that originated with a last universal common ancestor, and includes all its descendants. We can continue to use the category ‘life’ (lower case ‘l’) pragmatically to refer to similarities between various phenomena and Life. But the relevant similarities are a matter of interest and preference, not a matter of fact. The search for other life in the Universe, then, is merely a search for entities that resemble parts of Life in whatever sense astrobiologists find most appealing (e.g. metabolism, evolution, information, etc.). This does not mean that the search for evolved complexity elsewhere in the universe or its creation in the lab are futile endeavors, but that debates over whether they count as ‘life’ are. Ironically, finally abandoning the concept ‘life’ may make our searches for evolved complexity more fruitful. We explain why.

Keywords

Life Definitions of life LUCA Philosophy of astrobiology Origin of life Theory of life 

Notes

Acknowledgements

We thank the Natural Sciences and Engineering Research Council of Canada (Grant No. GLDSU/447989) for support, as well as the audiences in POBAM 2016, Duke University, University of Washington, Bryn Mawr College, University of Nevada, Reno, Dalhousie University, SoCIA 2018, Austin Booth, Letitia Meynell, Tyler D.P. Brunet, the editors, and several anonymous reviewers for valuable comments that helped improve this paper.

References

  1. Bedau, M. A. (2012). A functional account of degrees of minimal chemical life. Synthese, 185(1), 73–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Booth, A., Mariscal, C., & Doolittle, W. F. (2016). The modern synthesis in the light of microbial genomics. Annual Review of Microbiology, 70, 279–297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Boyd, R. (1991). Realism, anti-realism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philosphical Studies, 61(1), 127–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Boyd, R. (1999). Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In R. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 141–185). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  5. Chyba, C. F., & McDonald, G. D. (1995). The origin of life in the solar system: current issues. Annual Review of Earth and Planetary Sciences, 23(1), 215–249.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Cleland, C. E. (2004). Why it is a mistake to define ‘life’. In M. Bedau, P. Husbands, et al. (Eds.), Artificial life IX workshop proceedings (pp. 93–95).Google Scholar
  7. Cleland, C. E. (2006). Understanding the nature of life: A matter of definition or theory. In J. Seckbach (Ed.), Life as we know it. (Vol. 10 of the cellular origins, life in extreme habitats and astrobiology series) (pp. 589–600). Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  8. Cleland, C. E. (2012). Life without definitions. Synthese, 185(1), 125–144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Cleland, C. E., & Chyba, C. F. (2002). Defining ‘life’. Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, 32(4), 387–393.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Cleland, C. E., & Chyba, C. F. (2007). Does ‘life’ have a definition? In W. T. Sullivan III & J. Baross (Eds.), Planets and life: The emerging science of astrobiology (pp. 119–131). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Cleland, C. E., & Copley, S. D. (2005). The possibility of alternative microbial life on earth. International Journal of Astrobiology, 4(3–4), 165–173.  https://doi.org/10.1017/S147355040500279X.Google Scholar
  12. Darwin, C. (1859). On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life. London: Murray.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Davies, P. C., & Lineweaver, C. H. (2005). Finding a second sample of life on Earth. Astrobiology, 5(2), 154–163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. de Queiroz, K. (2005). Ernst Mayr and the modern concept of species. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 102, 6600–6607.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Dennett, D. C. (1997). Facing backwards on the problem of consciousness. In J. Shear (Ed.), Explaining consciousness: The hard problem. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  16. Dennett, D. C. (2016). Illusionism as the obvious default theory of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 23(11–12), 65–72.Google Scholar
  17. Descartes, R. (2010). Treatise on man. In M. A. Bedau & C. E. Cleland (Eds.), The nature of life: Classical and contemporary perspectives from philosophy and science. New York: Cambridge University Press, p. 15-20. 9-14. (Original translation published in 1985 by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch, Cambridge University Press. Original work published in 1664).Google Scholar
  18. Doolittle, W. F. (2014). Natural selection through survival alone, and the possibility of Gaia. Biology and Philosophy, 29(3), 415–423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Doolittle, W. F. (2017). Making the most of clade selection. Philosophy of Science, 84(2), 275–295.  https://doi.org/10.1086/690719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Doolittle, W. F., & Zhaxybayeva, O. (2009). On the origin of prokaryotic species. Genome Research, 19(5), 744–756.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Ellington, A. D. (2012). Origins for everyone. Evolution: Education and Outreach, 5(3), 361–366.Google Scholar
  22. Ereshefsky, M. (Ed.). (1992a). The units of evolution: essays on the nature of species. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  23. Ereshefsky, M. (1992b). Eliminative pluralism. Philosophy of Science, 59(4), 671–690.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Feinberg, G., & Shapiro, R. (1980). Life beyond earth: the intelligent earthling’s guide to life in the universe. New York: William Morrow.Google Scholar
  25. Ghiselin, M. T. (1974). A radical solution to the species problem. Systematic Biology, 23(4), 536–544.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Gibson, D. G., Glass, J. I., Lartigue, C., Noskov, V. N., Chuang, R. Y., Algire, M. A., et al. (2010). Creation of a bacterial cell controlled by a chemically synthesized genome. Science, 329(5987), 52–56.  https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1190719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Hermida, M. (2016). Life on earth is an individual. Theory in Biosciences, 135(1–2), 37–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Hull, D. L. (1976). Are species really individuals? Systematic Biology, 25(2), 174–191.Google Scholar
  29. Hull, D. L. (1978). A matter of individuality. Philosophy of Science, 45(3), 335–360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Hull, D. L. (1980). Individuality and selection. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 11, 3110332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Jabr, F. (2013). Why life does not really exist. Scientific American. http://blogs.scientificamerican.com/brainwaves/2013/12/02/why-life-does-not-really-exist/. Accessed May 29, 2014.
  32. Janković, S., & Ćirković, M. M. (2016). Evolvability is an evolved ability: The coding concept as the arch-unit of natural selection. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 46(1), 67–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Koonin, E. V. (2012). Defining life: an exercise in semantics or a route to biological insights? Journal of Biomolecular Structure & Dynamics, 29(4), 603–605.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Koonin, E. V., & Wolf, Y. I. (2010). The common ancestry of life. Biology Direct, 5, 64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Küppers, B. O. (1990). Information and the origin of life. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  36. Lahav, N. (1999). Biogenesis: Theories of life’s origin. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  37. Langton, C. G. (1989). Artificial life. Redwood City: Addison-Wesley Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  38. Lederberg, J. (1960). Exobiology: approaches to life beyond the earth. Science, 132(3424), 393–400, article stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1705846.
  39. Levin, G. V. (2010). It’s time to realize there is life on mars. EARTH, 86.Google Scholar
  40. Levin, G. V., & Straat, P. A. (1977). Life on mars? The Viking labeled release experiment. bio systems, 9(2–3), 165–174.  https://doi.org/10.1016/0303-2647(77)90026-0.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Machery, E. (2012). Why I stopped worrying about the definition of life… and why you should as well. Synthese, 185(1), 145–164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Malaterre, C. (2010). Lifeness signatures and the roots of the tree of life. Biology and Philosophy, 25, 643–658.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Mayr, E. (1998). This is biology: The science of the living world. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  44. Mishler, B. D., & Brandon, R. N. (1987). Individuality, pluralism, and the phylogenetic species concept. Biology and Philosophy, 2(4), 397–414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Mix, L. J. (2015). Defending definitions of life. Astrobiology, 15(1), 15–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Mix, L. J. (2016). Five lives. In Canadian society for the history and philosophy of science annual conference/Congrès Annuel de la Société Canadienne d’histoire et de philosophie des sciences. Presentation.Google Scholar
  47. Müller, H.J. (1926). The gene as the basis of life. In Proceedings of the 1st international congress of plant sciences, Ithaca, pp. 897–921.Google Scholar
  48. Oparin, A. (2010). The nature of life. (Original translation published in 1964 by Ann Synge, Charlotte Synge and Liz Smith, Academic Press, and Oliver and Boyd Ltd., Longman Publishing. Original work published in 1936).Google Scholar
  49. Pályi, G., Zucchi, C., & Caglioti, L. (Eds.). (2002). Fundamentals of life. New York: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  50. Plaxco, K. W., & Gross, M. (2006). Astrobiology: A brief introduction. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  51. Popa, R. (2004). Between necessity and probability: Searching for the definition and origin of life. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
  52. Sagan, C. (1970). Life. In Encyclopedia Britannica. Chicago, Ill.: Encyclopædia Britannica Incorporated, pp. 1083–1083A.Google Scholar
  53. Sagan, C. (1974). The origin of life in a cosmic context. Cosmochemical evolution and the origins of life (Vol. 5, pp. 497–505). Netherlands: Springer.Google Scholar
  54. Schrödinger, E. (1944). What is life?. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  55. Shields, C. (2015). De Anima, Translated with an introduction and commentary, Clarendon Aristotle Series. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  56. Slater, M. H. (2015). Natural kindness. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66(2), 375–411.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Smith, K. C. (2016). Life is hard: Countering definitional pessimism concerning the definition of life. International Journal of Astrobiology, 15(4), 277–289.  https://doi.org/10.1017/S1473550416000021.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Szostak, J. W. (2012). Attempts to define life do not help to understand the origin of life. Journal of Biomolecular Structure & Dynamics, 29(4), 599–600.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Theobald, D. L. (2010). A formal test of the theory of universal common ancestry. Nature, 465(7295), 219–222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Trifonov, E. N. (2011). Vocabulary of definitions of life suggests a definition. Journal of Biomolecular Structure and Dynamics, 29(2), 259–266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Tsokolov, S. A. (2009). Why is the definition of life so elusive? Epistemological considerations. .Astrobiology, 9(4), 401–412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Turner, J. S. (2004). Extended phenotypes and extended organisms. Biology and Philosophy, 19(3), 327–352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Wolfe, C. T. (2011). Vitalism. In M. Gargaud, et al. (Eds.), Encyclopedia of astrobiology (pp. 1740–1750). New York: Springer.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Philosophy, Ecology, Evolution and Conservation Biology (EECB) Program, Integrative Neuroscience ProgramUniversity of Nevada, RenoRenoUSA
  2. 2.Department of Biochemistry and Molecular BiologyDalhousie UniversityHalifaxCanada

Personalised recommendations