Is imagination too liberal for modal epistemology?
Abstract
Appealing to imagination for modal justification is very common. But not everyone thinks that all imaginings provide modal justification. Recently, Gregory (2010) and Kung (Philos Phenomenol Res 81(3):620–663, 2010) have independently argued that, whereas imaginings with sensory imageries can justify modal beliefs, those without sensory imageries don’t because of such imaginings’ extreme liberty. In this essay, I defend the general modal epistemological relevance of imagining. I argue, first, that when the objections that target the liberal nature of non-sensory imaginings are adequately developed, those objections also threaten the sensory imaginings. So, if we think that non-sensory imaginings are too liberal for modal justification, we should say the same about sensory imaginings. I’ll finish my defense by showing that, when it comes to deciding between saying that all imaginings are prima facie justificatory and saying that no imaginings are justificatory, there is an independent reason for accepting the former.
Keywords
Modal epistemology Modal skepticism ImaginationReferences
- Bealer, G. (2002). Modal epistemology and the rationalist renaissnce. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possiblity (pp. 71–125). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Benaceraff, P. (1973). Mathematical truth. Journal of Philosophy, 70(19), 661–679.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Berker, S. (2013). The rejection of epistemic consequentialism. Philosophical Issues, 23, 363–387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Byrne, A. (2007). Possibility and imagination. Philosophical Perspectives, 21(1), 125–144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Chan, T. (Ed.). (2009). The aim of belief. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
- Chisholm, R. (1980). A version of foundationalism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5(1), 543–564.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Cruz, J., & Pollock, J. (2004). The chimerical appeal of epistemic externalism. In R. Schantz (Ed.), The external challenge (pp. 125–142). Berlin: De GruyterGoogle Scholar
- Currie, G., & Ravenscroft, I. (2002). Recreative minds: Imagination in philosophy and psychology. Oxford: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (2009). Knowledge in an uncertain world. Oxford: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Fiocco, M. (2007). Conceivability, imagination, and modal knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74(2), 364–380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Geirsson, H. (2005). Conceivability and defeasible modal justification. Philosophical Studies, 122(3), 279–304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Gregory, D. (2010). Conceivability and apparent possibility. In B. Hale & A. Hoffmann (Eds.), Modality: Metaphysics, logic, and epistemology (pp. 319–341). Oxford: OUPGoogle Scholar
- Hartl, P. (2016). Modal scepticism, yablo-style conceivability, and analogical reasoning. Synthese, 193, 269–291.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Haslanger, S. (2000). Gender and race: (What) are they? (What) do we want them to be? Nous, 34(1), 31–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Haslanger, S. (2006). What good are our intuitions? Philosophical analysis and social kinds. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 80(1), 89–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Hawke, P. (2011). Van Inwagen’s modal skepticism. Philosophical Studies, 153(3), 351–364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Huemer, M. (2001). Skepticism and the veil of perception. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.Google Scholar
- Huemer, M. (2007). Compassionate phenomenal conservatism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74(1), 30–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Ichikawa, J., & Jarvis, B. (2012). Rational imagination and modal knowledge. Noûs, 46(1), 127–158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kung, P. (2010). Imagining as a guide to possibility. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81(3), 620–663.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kung, P. (2016). You really do imagine it: Against error theories of imagination. Noûs, 50(1), 90–120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kvanvig, J. (1989). Conservatism and its virtues. Synthese, 79, 143–163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Littlejohn, C. (2012). Justification and the truth-connection. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Maitzen, S. (1995). Our errant epistemic aim. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55(4), 869–876.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- McCain, K. (2008). The virtues of epistemic conservatism. Synthese, 164(2), 185–200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- McDowell, J. (2011). Perception as a capacity for knowledge. Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
- Montmarquet, J. (1993). Epistemic virtue and doxastic responsibility. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
- Peacocke, C. (2002). Being known. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
- Pryor, J. (2000). The skeptic and the dogmatist. Nous, 34(4), 517–549.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Quine, W. V. O. (1953a). From a Logical Point of View. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Quine, W. V. O. (1953b). Two dogmas of empiricism. In From a logical point of view (pp. 20–46). Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Roca-Royes, S. (2011). Conceivability and De Re modal knowledge. Noûs, 45(1), 22–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Schantz, R. (Ed.). (2004). The externalist challenge. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
- Steglich-Petersen, A. (2009). Truth as the aim of epistemic justification. In Chan (Ed.), The Aim of belief (pp. 204–226).Google Scholar
- Strawson, P. (1962). Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 1–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Van Inwagen, P. (1998). Modal epistemology. Philosophical Studies, 92(1), 67–84.Google Scholar
- Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Oxford: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Yablo, S. (1993). Is conceivability a guide to possibility? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53(1), 1–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar