Advertisement

Modal epistemology made concrete

  • Daniel Dohrn
Article
  • 79 Downloads

Abstract

Many philosophers since Hume have accepted that imagining/conceiving a scenario is our prime guide to knowing its possibility. Stephen Yablo provided a more systematic criterion: one is justified in judging that p is possible if one can imagine a world which one takes to verify p. I defend a version of Yablo’s criterion against van Inwagen’s moderate modal scepticism. Van Inwagen’s key argument is that we cannot satisfy Yablo’s criterion because we are not in a position to spell out far-fetched possible scenarios in relevant detail. Van Inwagen’s argument can be applied to the use of conceivability for everyday possibility claims, leaving us with the spectre of pervasive modal scepticism. In order to answer the sceptical threat, I combine van Inwagen’s main example with general considerations about the nature of metaphysical modality to motivate a version of Yablo’s criterion and show that it does not lead to scepticism. One structural condition of p being metaphysically possible is that it coheres with a complete reality. This condition gives rise to Yablo’s criterion. However, for the criterion to be of any avail, we have to disregard details we are not in a position to specify. To account for our practice of doing so, I use Yablo’s distinction between imagining a world as determinate and imagining it determinately. I present a condition when we may simply disregard details as determinate. The condition results from integrating analogical reasoning into the conceivability test.

Keywords

Modal Possibility Imagination Conceivability Conceiving Possible world Modal epistemology 

References

  1. Almog, J. (1996). The what and the how II: reals and mights. Noûs, 30, 413–433.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bealer, G. (2004). The origins of modal error. Dialectica, 58, 11–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Biggs, S. (2011). Abduction and modality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 83, 283–326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bueno, O., & Shalkowski, S. (2015). Modalism and theoretical virtues: toward an epistemology of modality. Philosophical Studies, 172, 671–689.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Byrne, A. (2007). Possibility and imagination. Philosophical Perspectives, 21, 125–144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Chalmers, D. (2002). Does conceivability entail possibility? In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possibility (pp. 71–125). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  7. Chudnoff, E. (2015). Phenomenal contrast arguments for cognitive phenomenology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 91, 82–104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Day, S. B., & Gentner, D. (2007). Non-intentional analogical inference in text-comprehension. Memory and Cognition, 35, 39–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Descartes, R. (1985). The philosophical writings of descartes I. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Evnine, S. (2008). Modal epistemology: our knowledge of necessity and possibility. Philosophy Compass, 3, 664–684.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fiocco, M. O. (2007). Conceivability, imagination and modal knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74, 364–380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Fischer, E. (2014). Philosophical intuitions, heuristics, and metaphors. Synthese, 191, 569–606.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Geirsson, H. (2005). Conceivability and defeasible modal justification. Philosophical Studies, 122, 279–304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Hale, B. (2002). Knowledge of necessity and possibility. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 103, 1–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Hartl, P. (2016). Modal scepticism, Yablo-style conceivability, and analogical reasoning. Synthese, 193, 269–291.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Hawke, P. (2011). Van Inwagen’s modal scepticism. Philosophical Studies, 153, 351–364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Hume, D. (1739–40). A treatise of human nature. Selby-Bigge (ed.) [1896]. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  18. Jackson, F. (2011). On gettier holdouts. Mind and Language, 26, 468–481.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Jenkins, C. (2010). Concepts, experience and modal knowledge. Philosophical Perspectives, 24, 255–278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Keynes, J. M. (1921). A treatise on probability. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  21. Kind, A. (2016). Imagining under constraints. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination (pp. 145–159). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Kment, B. (2012). Varieties of modality. In: E. N. Zalta (Ed.) The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2012 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/modality-varieties/.
  23. Kment, B. (2014). Modality and explanatory reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Kriegel, U. (2015). The varieties of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge/Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Kung, P. (2010). Imagining as a guide to possibility. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 620–663.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Kung, P. (2016). You really do imagine it: against error theories of imagination. Noûs, 50, 90–120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Leon, F. (2017). From modal scepticism to modal empiricism. In B. Fischer & F. Leon (Eds.), Modal epistemology after rationalism (pp. 247–262). Dordrecht: Synthese Library.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Lewis, D. (1986). Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow, Postscripts to ‘counterfactual dependence and times’s arrow’. In Philosophical papers II, 32-66. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  30. Lewis, D. (1994). Humean supervenience debugged. Mind, 103, 473–490.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Lowe, E. M. (2012). What is the source of our knowledge of modal truths? Mind, 121, 919–950.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Morreau, M. (2010). It simply doesn’t add up. Trouble with comparative similarity. Journal of Philosophy, 107, 469–490.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Peacocke, C. (2004). The realm of reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  34. Putnam, H. (1980). Brains and behavior. In N. Block (Ed.), Readings in philosophy of psychology (Vol. I, pp. 24–37). London: Methuen.Google Scholar
  35. Rasmussen, J. (2014). Continuity as a guide to possibility. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 92, 525–538.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Roca-Royes, S. (2017). Similarity and possibility: an epistemology of de re possibility for concrete entities. In B. Fischer & F. Leon (Eds.), Modal epistemology after rationalism (pp. 221–246). Dordrecht: Synthese Library.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Sider, T. (1993). Van Inwagen and the possibility of gunk. Analysis, 53, 285–289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Tidman, P. (1994). Conceivability as a test for possibility. American Philosophical Quarterly, 31, 297–309.Google Scholar
  39. Van Inwagen, P. (1998). Modal epistemology. Philosophical Studies, 92, 67–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Williams, R. (2006). Illusions of gunk. Philosophical Perspectives, 20, 493–513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Yablo, S. (1993). Is conceivability a guide to possibility? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53, 1–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Yablo, S. (2006). No fool’s cold. In M. Garçia-Carpintero & J. Macià (Eds.), Two-dimensional semantics (pp. 327–345). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institut für PhilosophieHU BerlinBerlinGermany

Personalised recommendations