Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 176, Issue 3, pp 819–826 | Cite as

A second-order intervention

  • Amanda Corris
  • Anthony ChemeroEmail author
Article

Most of Shaun Gallagher’s Enactivist Interventions into philosophical issues about the mind are quite effective, but there are a few that could be improved. In what follows, we attempt to make two of Gallagher’s arguments more convincing. Our focus will be on Gallagher’s use of Francisco Varela’s “threefold distinction in temporal and dynamical registers” (Gallagher 2017, 8; Varela 1999). Gallagher uses this threefold distinction to address issues concerning what he calls the “causal-constitution fallacy” and issues concerning neuroscientific findings and free will. Gallagher is less convincing than he could be when he addresses these issues, because although he invokes Varela’s threefold distinction, he does not also provide a detailed story about how these “temporal and dynamical registers” relate to one another. We will provide a counter-intuitive, but empirically well-supported story about how the registers relate to one another, and, in so doing, improve upon Gallagher’s...

Notes

References

  1. Abney, D., Paxton, A., Dale, R., & Kello, C. T. (2014). Complexity matching in dyadic conversation. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 143, 2304–2315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14(1), 43–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Anderson, M. L. (2014). After phrenology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Anderson, M. L., Richardson, M. J., & Chemero, A. (2012). Eroding the boundaries of cognition: Implications of embodiment. Topics in Cognitive Science, 4, 717–730.  https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1756-8765.2012.01211.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (2010). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. MIT Press. (Originally published by Princeton University Press, 1993).Google Scholar
  6. Chemero, A. (2016). Sensorimotor empathy. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 23(5–6), 138–152.Google Scholar
  7. Craver, C. F., & Bechtel, W. (2007). Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biology and Philosophy, 22(4), 547–563.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Deacon, T. W. (2011). Incomplete nature: How mind emerged from matter. New York: WW Norton & Company.Google Scholar
  9. Dotov, D. G., Nie, L., & Chemero, A. (2010). A demonstration of the transition from ready-to-hand to unready-to-hand. PLoS ONE, 5(3), e9433.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Haken, H. (1977). Synergetics. Physics Bulletin, 28(9), 412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Ihlen, E. A. F., & Vereijken, B. (2010). Interaction-dominant dynamics in human cognition: Beyond 1/fα fluctuation. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 139(3), 436–463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Kelso, J. A. S. (1995). Dynamic patterns. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  14. Kelso, J. A. S. (2008). An essay on understanding the mind. Ecological Psychology, 20(2), 180–208.  https://doi.org/10.1080/10407410801949297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Libet, B. (1985). Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8(4), 529–539.  https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00044903.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Libet, B. (1999). Do we have free will? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6(8–9), 47–57.Google Scholar
  17. Nalepka, P., Kallen, R. W., Chemero, A., Saltzman, E., & Richardson, M. J. (2017). Herd those sheep: Emergent multiagent coordination and behavioral-mode switching. Psychological Science, 28(5), 630–650.  https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797617692107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Paxton, A., & Dale, R. (2013). Argument disrupts interpersonal synchrony. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 66, 2092–2102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Riley, M. A., Richardson, M., Shockley, K., & Ramenzoni, V. C. (2011). Interpersonal synergies. Frontiers in Psychology, 2, 38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Van Orden, G. C., Holden, J. G., & Turvey, M. T. (2003). Self-organization of cognitive performance. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 132(3), 331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Van Orden, G. C., Holden, J. G., & Turvey, M. T. (2005). Human cognition and 1/f scaling. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 134(1), 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Van Orden, G., Hollis, G., & Wallot, S. (2012). The blue-collar brain. Frontiers in Physiology, 3, 207.Google Scholar
  23. Varela, F. J. (1999). The specious present: A neurophenomenology of time consciousness. In J. Petitot, F. J. Varela, B. Pachoud, & J.-M. Roy (Eds.), Naturalizing phenomenology: issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science (pp. 266–314). Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Wagenmakers, E. J., Farrell, S., & Ratcliff, R. (2004). Estimation and interpretation of 1/f α noise in human cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 11(4), 579–615.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. West, G. (2016). Scale. New York: Penguin.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of CincinnatiCincinnatiUSA

Personalised recommendations