Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 176, Issue 2, pp 483–501 | Cite as

Possessing epistemic reasons: the role of rational capacities

  • Eva SchmidtEmail author
Article
  • 340 Downloads

Abstract

In this paper, I defend a reasons-first view of epistemic justification, according to which the justification of our beliefs arises entirely in virtue of the epistemic reasons we possess. I remove three obstacles for this view, which result from its presupposition that epistemic reasons have to be possessed by the subject: (1) the problem that reasons-first accounts of justification are necessarily circular; (2) the problem that they cannot give special epistemic significance to perceptual experience; (3) the problem that they have to say that implicit biases provide epistemic. The first problem will be overcome by introducing presentational attitudes that are not in need of justification as basic ways of possessing epistemic reasons. The latter two problems will be solved by introducing epistemic rational capacities of two different kinds, which are exercised in mental states that are ways of possessing epistemic reasons, and by distinguishing these from mental states that are not exercises of epistemic rational capacities .

Keywords

Epistemic reasons Reasons-first epistemology Justification Possessing reasons Superblindsight Implicit bias Rational capacities Virtue epistemology 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I’d like to thank participants of the conference on rational capacities at the University of Luxembourg for extremely helpful comments, in particular Alex Gregory, David Löwenstein, Susanne Mantel, and Daniel Star. I'm grateful for feedback on the manuscript to Hanjo Glock, Susanne Mantel (again), Anne Meylan, Oliver Petersen, Peter Schulte, and Daniel Whiting. Finally, I wish to thank an anonymous referee for this journal, who did an exemplary job.

References

  1. Anscombe, G. E. M. (1963). Intention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Beddor, B. (2015). Evidentialism, circularity, and grounding. Philosophical Studies, 172, 1847–1868.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Beddor, B. (2016) Reduction in epistemology. Dissertation. https://rucore.libraries.rutgers.edu/rutgers-lib/49910/PDF/1/.
  4. Block, N. (1995). On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Brain and Behavioral Sciences, 18, 227–247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. BonJour, L. (1980). Externalist theories of empirical knowledge. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5, 53–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Byrne, A. (2016). The epistemic significance of experience. Philosophical Studies, 173, 947–967.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Dancy, J. (2004). Ethics without principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Gendler, T. S. (2008). Alief and belief. Journal of Philosophy, 105, 634–663.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Goldman, A. (2011). Toward a synthesis of reliabilism and evidentialism? In T. Dougherty (Ed.), Evidentialism and its discontents (pp. 254–820). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Holroyd, J. (2012). Responsibility for implicit bias. Journal of Social Philosophy, 43, 274–306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Kornblith, H. (2015). The role of reasons in epistemology. Episteme, 12, 225–239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Lai, C., et al. (2016). Reducing implicit racial preferences: II. Intervention effectiveness across time. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 145, 1001–1016.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. McDowell, J. (2011). Perception as a capacity for knowledge. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Schellenberg, S. (2016). Phenomenal evidence and factive evidence. Philosophical Studies, 173, 875–896.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Schmidt, E. (2017). New trouble for reasons as evidence: Means that don’t justify the ends. Ethics, 127, S. 708–718.Google Scholar
  16. Schmidt, E. (forthcoming). Subjective normative reasons for mentalism. In C. Kyriacou & R. McKenna (Eds.), Epistemic realism and antirealism: Approaches to metaepistemology. London: Palgrave.Google Scholar
  17. Schmidt, E. (n.d.). Seeing isn’t believing: An argument for reasons-first epistemology.Google Scholar
  18. Schroeder, M. (2008). Having reasons. Philosophical Studies, 139, 57–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Schroeder, M. (2011). What does it take to ‘have’ a reason? In A. Reisner & A. Steglich-Petersen (Eds.), Reasons for belief (pp. 201–222). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Siegel, S. (2013). Can selection effects on experience influence its rational role? In T. Gendler (Ed.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 4, pp. 240–270). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology: Apt belief and reflective knowledge (Vol. II). Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Steinpreis, R., et al. (1999). The Impact of gender on the review of the curricula vitae of job applicants and tenure candidates: A national empirical study. Sex Roles, 41, 509–528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Sylvan, K., & Sosa, E. (forthcoming). The place of reasons in epistemology. In D. Star (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of reasons and normativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of ZürichZurichSwitzerland

Personalised recommendations