Advertisement

Natural Language Semantics

, Volume 27, Issue 4, pp 279–321 | Cite as

Licensing of PPI indefinites: Movement or pseudoscope?

  • Vincent HomerEmail author
  • Rajesh Bhatt
Article

Abstract

Positive Polarity indefinites (PPI indefinites), such as some in English, are licensed in simplex negative sentences as long as they take wide scope over negation. When it surfaces under a clausemate negation, some can in principle take wide scope either by movement or by some semantic mechanism; e.g., it can take pseudoscope if it is interpreted as a choice function variable. Therefore, there is some uncertainty regarding the way in which PPI indefinites get licensed: can pseudoscope suffice? In this article we show, using novel data from Hindi-Urdu and English, that pseudoscope is not sufficient, and that it is the syntactic position of PPI indefinites at LF, rather than their actual scope, which is relevant for licensing. These facts support a unified view of PPI indefinites as generalized quantifiers, and disfavor analyses where they are, or can be, interpreted as choice function variables.

Keywords

Positive polarity Hindi-Urdu Indefinites Choice functions Pseudoscope Exhaustification 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

Acknowledgements

This article has benefitted from feedback from audiences at UMass, FASAL 5 at Yale, the session on ‘Varieties of Positive Polarity Items’ at the 2015 DGfS in Leipzig, TbiLLC 2015, NELS 46 at Concordia University, SinFonIJA 9 in Brno, the 2017 GLOW in Asia at the National University of Singapore, the University of Edinburgh, the University of Ottawa, and MIT. We have specially benefitted from feedback by Ana Arregui, Simon Charlow, Veneeta Dayal, Ashwini Deo, Irene Heim, Caroline Heycock, Kyle Johnson, Stefan Keine, Dennis Ott, Ezer Rasin, and Roger Schwarzschild. Our thanks also go to the NALS anonymous reviewers and to our editor, Angelika Kratzer.

References

  1. Abusch, Dorit. 1993. The scope of indefinites. Natural Language Semantics 2: 83–135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Baker, Carl Leroy. 1970. Double negatives. Linguistic Inquiry 1: 169–186.Google Scholar
  3. Brasoveanu, Adrian, Donka Farkas, and Floris Roelofsen. 2013. N-words and sentential negation: Evidence from polarity particles and VP ellipsis. Semantics and Pragmatics 6: 1–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bruening, Benjamin. 2001. QR obeys superiority: Frozen scope and ACD. Linguistic Inquiry 32: 233–273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Büring, Daniel. 2005. Binding theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Chierchia, Gennaro. 2001. A puzzle about indefinites. In Semantic interfaces: Reference, anaphora, and aspect, ed. C. Cecchetto, G. Chierchia, and M.T. Guasti, 51–89. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  7. Chierchia, Gennaro. 2004. Scalar implicatures, polarity phenomena, and the syntax/pragmatics interface. In Structures and beyond, ed. A. Belletti, 39–103. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Chierchia, Gennaro. 2006. Broaden your views: Implicatures of domain widening and the “logicality” of language. Linguistic Inquiry 37: 535–590.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Chierchia, Gennaro. 2013. Logic in grammar: Polarity, free choice, and intervention. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Dayal, Veneeta Srivastav. 1994. Binding facts in Hindi and the scrambling phenomenon. In Theoretical perspectives on word order in South Asian languages (CSLI Lecture Notes 50), ed. Miriam Butt, Tracy Holloway King, and Gillian Ramchand, 237–262. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  11. de Swart, Henriëtte. 1998. Licensing of negative polarity items under inverse scope. Lingua 105: 175–200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. de Swart, Henriëtte. 2000. Scope ambiguities with negative quantifiers. In Reference and anaphoric relations, ed. Klaus von Heusinger and Urs Egli, 109–132. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  13. Farkas, Donka. 1981. Quantifier scope and syntactic islands. In Papers from the 17th regional meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, ed. Randall Hendrick, Carrie Masek, and Mary Frances Miller, 59–66. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.Google Scholar
  14. Ferreira, Fernanda, and Naomi Patson. 2007. The “good enough” approach to language comprehension. Language and Linguistics Compass 1: 71–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Fodor, Janet, and Ivan Sag. 1982. Referential and quantificational indefinites. Linguistics and Philosophy 5: 355–398.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Gajewski, Jon. 2002. On analyticity in natural language. Ms.: University of Connecticut.Google Scholar
  17. Gajewski, Jon. 2005. Neg-raising: Polarity and presupposition. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.Google Scholar
  18. Geurts, Bart. 1996. On no. Journal of Semantics 13: 67–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Grodzinsky, Yosef, and Tanya Reinhart. 1993. The innateness of binding and coreference. Linguistic Inquiry 24: 69–102.Google Scholar
  20. Heim, Irene. 1982. The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. Doctoral dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.Google Scholar
  21. Hoji, Hajime. 1985. Logical form constraints and configurational structures in Japanese. Doctoral dissertation, University of Washington.Google Scholar
  22. Homer, Vincent. 2011. Polarity and modality. Doctoral dissertation, UCLA.Google Scholar
  23. Homer, Vincent. 2013. Epistemic modals: High ma non troppo. In Proceedings of NELS 40, ed. Seda Kan, Claire Moore-Cantwell, and Robert Staubs, 273–287. Amherst, MA: GLSA.Google Scholar
  24. Homer, Vincent. 2015. Neg-raising and positive polarity: The view from modals. Semantics and Pragmatics 8: 1–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Homer, Vincent. 2019. Domains of polarity items. To appear in Journal of Semantics.Google Scholar
  26. Hook, Peter Edwin. 1973. The compound verb in Hindi. Doctoral dissertation, University of Pennsylvania.Google Scholar
  27. Iatridou, Sabine, and Ivy Sichel. 2009. Negative DPs and scope diminishment: Some basic patterns. In Proceedings of NELS 38, ed. Anisa Schardl, Martin Walkow, and Muhammad Abdurrahman, 411–424. Amherst, MA: GLSA.Google Scholar
  28. Jacobs, Joachim. 1980. Lexical decomposition in Montague grammar. Theoretical Linguistics 7: 121–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Johnson, Kyle, and Satoshi Tomioka. 1998. Lowering and mid-size clauses. In Proceedings of the 1997 Tübingen Workshop on Reconstruction, ed. Graham Katz, Shin-Sook Kim, and Winhart Haike, 185–206. Tübingen: Sprachtheoretische Grundlagen für die Computerlinguistik.Google Scholar
  30. Kidwai, Ayesha. 2000. XP-adjunction in universal grammar: Scrambling and binding in Hindi-Urdu. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  31. King, Jeff C. 1988. Are indefinite descriptions ambiguous? Philosophical Studies 53: 417–440.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Koller, Alexander, and Joachim Niehren. 1999. Scope underspecification and processing. Lecture Notes, ESSLLI ’99, Utrecht, The Netherlands.Google Scholar
  33. Kratzer, Angelika. 1995. Stage-level and individual-level predicates. In The generic book, ed. Gregory N. Carlson and Francis Jeffry Pelletier, 125–175. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  34. Kratzer, Angelika. 1998. Scope or pseudoscope? Are there wide-scope indefinites? In Events and Grammar, ed. Susan Rothstein, 163–196. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Kroch, Anthony S. 1979. The semantics of scope in English. New York: Garland.Google Scholar
  36. Kumar, Rajesh. 2006. The syntax of negation and the licensing of negative polarity items in Hindi. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  37. Kuno, Susumu. 1973. The structure of the Japanese language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  38. Ladusaw, William A. 1980. Polarity sensitivity as inherent scope relations. New York: Garland.Google Scholar
  39. Lahiri, Utpal. 1998. Focus and negative polarity in Hindi. Natural Language Semantics 6: 57–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Larson, Richard. 1990. Double objects revisited: Reply to Jackendoff. Linguistic Inquiry 21: 589–632.Google Scholar
  41. Linebarger, Marcia C. 1980. The grammar of negative polarity. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.Google Scholar
  42. Linebarger, Marcia C. 1987. Negative polarity and grammatical representation. Linguistics and Philosophy 10: 325–387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Mahajan, Anoop Kumar. 1990a. The A/A-bar distinction and movement theory. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.Google Scholar
  44. Mahajan, Anoop Kumar. 1990b. LF conditions on negative polarity licensing. Lingua 80: 333–348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Mahajan, Anoop Kumar. 1997. Rightward scrambling. In Rightward movement, ed. Dorothee Beerman, David LeBlanc, and Henk van Riemsdijk, 185–213. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Matthewson, Lisa. 1999. On the interpretation of wide-scope indefinites. Natural Language Semantics 7: 79–134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. May, Robert. 1977. The grammar of quantification. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.Google Scholar
  48. Montague, Richard M. 1973. The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In Formal philosophy, ed. R.H. Thomason, 247–270. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  49. Nakanishi, Kimiko. 2001. Indefinites and frozen scope in Japanese: Restriction on QR and choice functions. In Proceedings of WCCFL 20, ed. K. Megerdoomian and L.A. Barel, 456–469. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.Google Scholar
  50. Nevins, Andrew, and Pranav Anand. 2003. Some AGREEment matters. In Proceedings of WCCFL 22, ed. Gina Garding and Mimu Tsujimura, 370–383. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.Google Scholar
  51. Nicolae, Andreea Cristina. 2012a. Negation-resistant polarity items. Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 9: 225–242.Google Scholar
  52. Nicolae, Andreea Cristina. 2012b. Positive polarity items: An alternative-based account. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 16, ed. Ana Aguilar Guevara, Anna Chernilovskaya, and Rick Nouwen, 475–488. Cambridge, MA: MITWPL.Google Scholar
  53. Pandit, Ira. 1985. Exceptions to weak and strong crossover in Hindi. Linguistic Inquiry 16: 678–681.Google Scholar
  54. Penka, Doris. 2007. Negative indefinites. Doctoral dissertation, Universität Tübingen.Google Scholar
  55. Reinhart, Tanya. 1997. Quantifier scope: How labor is divided between QR and choice functions. Linguistics and Philosophy 20: 335–397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Richards, Norvin. 1997. What moves where when in which language? Doctoral dissertation, MIT.Google Scholar
  57. Rullmann, Hotze. 1995. Geen einheid. Tabu: Bulletin voor Taalwetenschap 25: 194–197.Google Scholar
  58. Ruys, Eddy. 1992. The scope of indefinites. Doctoral dissertation, University of Utrecht.Google Scholar
  59. Sanford, Anthony J., and Patrick Sturt. 2002. Depth of processing in language comprehension: Not noticing the evidence. Trends in Cognitive Science 6: 382–386.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Schwarzschild, Roger. 2002. Singleton indefinites. Journal of Semantics 19: 289–314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Szabolcsi, Anna. 2004. Positive polarity—negative polarity. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 22: 409–452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Szabolcsi, Anna. 2010. Quantification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Uribe-Etxebarria, Myriam. 1994. Interface licensing conditions on negative polarity items: A theory of polarity and tense interactions. Doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut.Google Scholar
  64. Uribe-Etxebarria, Myriam. 1996. Levels of representation and negative polarity item licensing. In Proceedings of WCCFL 14, ed. J. Camacho, L. Choueiri, and M. Watanabe, 571–586. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  65. van der Wouden, Tom. 1997. Negative contexts. Collocation, polarity and multiple negation. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  66. von Fintel, Kai. 1999. NPI licensing, Strawson entailment, and context dependency. Journal of Semantics 16: 97–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Winter, Yoad. 1997. Choice functions and the scopal semantics of indefinites. Linguistics and Philosophy 20: 399–467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. Zeijlstra, Hedde. 2017. Universal quantifier PPIs. Glossa: A Journal of General Linguistics 2: 1–25.Google Scholar
  69. Zeijlstra, Hedde, and Doris Penka. 2005. Negative indefinites in Dutch and German. Ms., Universität Tübingen.Google Scholar
  70. Zwarts, Frans. 1998. Three types of polarity. Plurality and Quantification 69: 177–238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.UMass-Amherst Linguistics DepartmentUMass-AmherstAmherstUSA
  2. 2.CNRS-Jean NicodParisFrance

Personalised recommendations