Advertisement

Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics

, Volume 40, Issue 6, pp 523–538 | Cite as

Conscience-based refusal of patient care in medicine: a consequentialist analysis

  • Udo SchuklenkEmail author
Article

Abstract

Conscience-based refusals by health care professionals to provide care to eligible patients are problematic, given the monopoly such professionals hold on the provision of such services. This article reviews standard ethical arguments in support of conscientious refuser accommodation and finds them wanting. It discusses proposed compromise solutions involving efforts aimed at testing the genuineness and reasonability of refusals and rejects those solutions too. A number of jurisdictions have introduced policies requiring conscientious refusers to provide effective referrals. These policies have turned out to be unworkable. They subject patients to a health care delivery lottery, which is incompatible with the fundamental values of medical professionalism. This paper sheds light on transnational efforts aimed at undermining progress made in reproductive health by means of conscientious refusal accommodation claims. The view that the accommodation of conscientious refusers is indefensible on consequentialist ethical grounds, as well as on grounds related to medical professionalism itself, is defended.

Keywords

Conscientious objection Medical professionalism Reproductive health Euthanasia Conscientious refusal 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I thank Jason T. Eberl and Ricardo D. Smalling as well as an anonymous reviewer chosen by this journal for their detailed, constructive comments on an earlier version of this paper. Their valiant critical efforts triggered numerous changes to the manuscript. A very special thank you is due to this journal’s Managing Editor at the time of writing, Katelyn MacDougald, a doctoral student in Georgetown University’s Department of Linguistics—a genius copy editor if there ever was one, and here’s hoping that she doesn’t have to correct this line. All remaining errors are my own.

References

  1. 1.
    Truong, Michelle, and Susan Y. Wood. 2018. Unconscionable: When providers deny abortion care. New York: International Women’s Health Coalition.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    NeJaime, Douglas, and Reva B. Siegel. 2015. Conscience wars: Complicity-based conscience claims in religion and politics. Yale Law Journal 124: 2516–2591.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Mississippi Health Care Right of Conscience Act, Miss. Code Ann. § 41-107-1 to 13 (2005).Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    NeJaime, Douglas, and Reva Siegel. 2018. Conscience wars in transnational perspective: Religious liberty, third-party harm, and pluralism. In The conscience wars: Rethinking the balance between religion, identity, and equality, ed. Susanna Mancini and Michel Rosenfeld, 187–219. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. 5.
    Charo, R. Alta. 2005. The celestial fire of conscience—refusing to deliver medical care. New England Journal of Medicine 352: 2471–2473.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. 6.
    Chavkin, Wendy, Liddy Leitman, and Kate Polin. 2013. Conscientious objection and refusal to provide reproductive healthcare: A white paper examining prevalence, health consequences, and policy responses. International Journal of Gynecology and Obstetrics 123(S3): S41–S56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. 7.
    Savulescu, Julian, and Udo Schuklenk. 2018. Conscientious objection and compromising the patient: Response to Hughes. Bioethics 32: 473–476.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. 8.
    Myran, Daniel T., Jillian Bardsley, Tania El Hindi, and Kristine Whitehead. 2018. Abortion education in Canadian family medicine residency programs. BMC Medical Education 18: 121.  https://doi.org/10.1186/s12909-018-1237-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. 9.
    Kirkey, Sharon. 2018. New family doctors “don’t feel competent” to perform abortions due to lack of training: Study. National Post, June 20. http://nationalpost.com/wcm/38b00c8e-1037-4174-b8d9-406b739db169.
  10. 10.
    Nelson, Lawrence. 2018. Provider conscientious refusal of abortion, obstetrical emergencies, and criminal homicide law. American Journal of Bioethics 18(7): 43–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. 11.
    Fiala, Christian, and Joyce H. Arthur. 2014. “Dishonourable disobedience”—why refusal to treat in reproductive healthcare is not conscientious objection. Woman Psychosomatic Gynecology and Obstetrics 1: 12–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. 12.
    United Nations Human Rights Committee. 1993. General comment No. 22, Article 18 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, 48th Sess., U.N. Doc. CCPR/C/48/CRP.2/Rev.1 (July 30, 1993). https://www.refworld.org/docid/453883fb22.html.
  13. 13.
    Brock, Peter. 1972. Pacifism in Europe to 1914. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    World Medical Association. 2017. WMA Declaration of Geneva. https://www.wma.net/policies-post/wma-declaration-of-geneva.
  15. 15.
    Kelly, Grant. 2017. Canadian doctors turn away from assisted dying over fees. Globe and Mail, July 3. https://www.theglobeandmail.com/news/national/payment-complications-turning-canadian-doctors-away-from-assisted-dying/article35538666.
  16. 16.
    Sulmasy, Daniel P. 2008. What is conscience and why is respect for it so important? Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 29: 135–149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. 17.
    Wicclair, Mark R. 2000. Conscientious objection in medicine. Bioethics 14: 205–227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. 18.
    Braun, Hannelore. 2000. Hermann Stöhr (1898–1940). In Zeugen einer besseren Welt: Christliche Märtyrer des 20. Jahrhunderts, ed. Karl-Joseph Hummel and Christoph Strohm, 87–105. Leipzig: Butzon and Bercker.Google Scholar
  19. 19.
    Wicclair, Mark R. 2011. Conscientious objection in health care: An ethical analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. 20.
    Cowley, Christopher. 2016. A defence of conscientious objection in medicine: A reply to Schuklenk and Savulescu. Bioethics 30: 358–364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. 21.
    Maclure, Jocelyn, and Isabelle Dumont. 2017. Selling conscience short: A response to Schuklenk and Smalling on conscientious objections by medical professionals. Journal of Medical Ethics 43: 241–244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. 22.
    Savulescu, Julian, and Udo Schuklenk. 2017. Doctors have no right to refuse medical assistance in dying, abortion or contraception. Bioethics 31: 162–170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. 23.
    Cholbi, Michael. 2018. Public cartels, private conscience. Politics, Philosophy and Economics 17: 356–377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. 24.
    Freidson, Eliot. 1989. Theory and the professions. Indiana Law Journal 64: 423–432.Google Scholar
  25. 25.
    Caruk, Holly, and Bryce Hoye. 2017. Waiting to die: Winnipeg man says faith-based hospital delayed access to assisted death. CBC News, October 26. https://www.cbc.ca/news/canada/manitoba/misericordia-assisted-dying-maid-1.4371796.
  26. 26.
    Lucero, Louis, II. 2018. Walgreens pharmacist denies woman with unviable pregnancy the medication needed to end it. New York Times, June 25. https://nyti.ms/2MY1zMv.
  27. 27.
    Porter, Tom. 2018. Walgreens pharmacy refuses to give woman pregnancy termination drugs prescribed by her doctor. Newsweek, June 24. http://www.newsweek.com/woman-refused-pregnancy-termination-drugs-walgreens-pharmacy-992994.
  28. 28.
    Schuklenk, Udo, and Ricardo Smalling. 2017. Why medical professionals have no moral claim to conscientious objection accommodation in liberal democracies. Journal of Medical Ethics 43: 234–240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. 29.
    Schuklenk, Udo. 2018. Conscientious objection in medicine: Accommodation versus professionalism and the public good. British Medical Bulletin 126: 47–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. 30.
    Myers, Christopher, and Robert D. Woods. 2007. Conscientious objection? Yes, but make sure it is genuine. American Journal of Bioethics 7(6): 19–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. 31.
    Kantymir, Lori, and Carolyn McLeod. 2014. Justification for conscience exceptions in health care. Bioethics 28: 16–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. 32.
    Card, Robert F. 2014. Reasonability and conscientious objection in medicine: A reply to Marsh and an elaboration of the reason-giving requirement. Bioethics 28: 320–326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. 33.
    Zolf, Benjamin. 2019. No conscientious objection without normative justification: Against conscientious objection in medicine. Bioethics 33: 146–153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. 34.
    Employment Division, Department of Human Resources of Oregon v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872 (1990).Google Scholar
  35. 35.
    Hughes, Jonathan A. 2018. Conscientious objection, professional duty and compromise: A response to Savulescu and Schuklenk. Bioethics 32: 126–131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. 36.
    Christian Medical and Dental Society of Canada v. College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario, 2018 ONSC 579.Google Scholar
  37. 37.
    Fiala, Christian, Kristina Gemzell Danielsson, Oskari Heikinheimo, Jans A. Guðmundsson, and Joyce Arthur. 2016. Yes we can! Successful examples of disallowing ‘conscientious objection’ in reproductive health care. European Journal of Contraception and Reproductive Health Care 21: 201–206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. 38.
    Gavaghan, Colin. 2017. Commentary on Hallagan v Medical Council of New Zealand: Whose choice, whose conscience? In Feminist judgments of Aotearoa New Zealand—Te Rino: A two-stranded rope, ed. Elisabeth McDonald, Rhonda Powell, Māmari Stephens, and Rosemary Hunter, 143–150. Oxford: Hart.Google Scholar
  39. 39.
    Baumgartner, Fritz. 2017. Has modern bioethics become a menace to ethical medicine? Celebrate Life Magazine. https://www.clmagazine.org/topic/medicine-science/has-modern-bioethics-become-a-menace-to-ethical-medicine. Accessed 27 June 2018.

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyQueen’s UniversityKingstonCanada

Personalised recommendations