Abstract
Douglas Diekema has argued that it is not the best interest standard, but the harm principle that serves as the moral basis for ethicists, clinicians, and the courts to trigger state intervention to limit parental authority in the clinic. Diekema claims the harm principle is especially effective in justifying state intervention in cases of religiously motivated medical neglect in pediatrics involving Jehovah’s Witnesses and Christian Scientists. I argue that Diekema has not articulated a harm principle that is capable of justifying state intervention in these cases. Where disagreements over appropriate care are tethered to metaphysical disagreements (as they are for Jehovah’s Witnesses and Christian Scientists), it is moral-metaphysical standards, rather than merely moral standards, that are needed to provide substantive guidance. I provide a discussion of Diekema’s harm principle to the broader end of highlighting an inconsistency between the theory and practice of secular bioethics when overriding religiously based medical decisions. In a secular state, ethicists, clinicians, and the courts are purportedly neutral with respect to moral-metaphysical positions, especially regarding those claims considered to be religious. However, the practice of overriding religiously based parental requests requires doffing the mantle of neutrality. In the search for a meaningful standard by which to override religiously based parental requests in pediatrics, bioethicists cannot avoid some minimal metaphysical commitments. To resolve this inconsistency, bioethicists must either begin permitting religiously based requests, even at the cost of children’s lives, or admit that at least some moral-metaphysical disputes can be rationally adjudicated.
Keywords
Harm principle Medical neglect Parental refusals Children Best interests Metaphysics Religious beliefNotes
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Jeffrey Bishop, Erica Salter, Stephanie Cargill, and Harold Braswell for their guidance in the preparation of this manuscript, as well as the reviewers and editorial staff at Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics for their help refining and clarifying my arguments.
Compliance with ethical standards
Conflict of interest
The authors declare to have no conflicts of interest.
References
- 1.Salter, Erica K. 2012. Deciding for a child: A comprehensive analysis of the best interest standard. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 33: 179–198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 2.Lo, Bernard. 2009. Resolving ethical dilemmas: A guide for clinicians. 4th ed. Philadelphia: Kluwer.Google Scholar
- 3.Kopelman, Loretta M. 1997. The best-interests standard as threshold, ideal, and standard of reasonableness. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 4.Brierley, Joe, Jim Linthicum, and Andy Petros. 2012. Should religious beliefs be allowed to stonewall a secular approach to withdrawing and withholding treatment in children? Journal of Medical Ethics 39: 573–577.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 5.Buchanan, Allen E., and Dan W. Brock. 1989. Deciding for others: The ethics of surrogate decision making. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
- 6.Linnard-Palmer, Luanne, and Susan Kools. 2004. Parents’ refusal of medical treatment based on religious and/or cultural beliefs: The law, ethical principles, and clinical implications. Journal of Pediatric Nursing 19: 351–356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 7.Diekema, Douglas S. 2004. Parental refusals of medical treatment: The harm principle as threshold for state intervention. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 25: 243–264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 8.Diekema, Douglas S. 2011. Revisiting the best interest standard: Uses and misuses. Journal of Clinical Ethics 22: 128–133.Google Scholar
- 9.Shah, Seema K., Abby R. Rosenberg, and Douglas S. Diekema. 2017. Charlie Gard and the limits of best interests. JAMA Pediatrics 171: 937–938.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 10.Diekema, Douglas S., Mark R. Mercurio, and Mary B. Adam. 2011. Clinical ethics in pediatrics: A case-based textbook. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 11.Rebecca, Dresser. 2003. Standards for family decisions: Replacing best interests with harm prevention. American Journal of Bioethics 3(2): 54–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 12.Elliston, Sarah. 2007. The best interests of the child in healthcare. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
- 13.Gillam, Lynn. 2016. The zone of parental discretion: An ethical tool for dealing with disagreement between parents and doctors about medical treatment for a child. Clinical Ethics 11: 1–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 14.McDougall, Rosalind J., and Lauren Notini. 2014. Overriding parents’ medical decisions for their children: A systematic review of normative literature. Journal of Medical Ethics 40: 448–452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 15.Birchley, Giles. 2016. Harm is all you need? Best interests and disputes about parental decision-making. Journal of Medical Ethics 42: 111–115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 16.Lowe, E.J. 2002. A survey of metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- 17.Timmons, Mark. 2013. Moral theory: An introduction. 2nd ed. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
- 18.Moreno, Jonathan D. 1995. Deciding together: Bioethics and moral consensus. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- 19.Mill, John Stuart. 1993. Utilitarianism. In On liberty and utilitarianism, 153–236. New York: Bantam.Google Scholar
- 20.Feinberg, Joel. 1984. The moral limits of the criminal law, Vol. 1: Harm to others. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- 21.Lantos, John D. 1997. Do we still need doctors? A physician’s personal account of practicing medicine today. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
- 22.Ross, Lainie Friedman. 1998. Children, families, and health care decision making. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- 23.Dworkin, Gerald. 1982. Consent, representation, and proxy consent. In Who speaks for the child: The problems of proxy consent, ed. Willard Gaylin and Ruth Macklin, 191–208. New York: Plenum.Google Scholar
- 24.Traugott, Isabel, and Ann Alpers. 1997. In their own hands: Adolescents’ refusals of medical treatment. Archives of Pediatrics and Adolescent Medicine 151: 922–927.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 25.Shah, Seema K., Abby R. Rosenberg, and Douglas S. Diekema. 2018. Charlie Gard and the limits of the harm principle—reply. JAMA Pediatrics 172: 301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 26.Birchley, Giles. 2016. The harm threshold and parents’ obligation to benefit their children. Journal of Medical Ethics 42: 123–126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 27.Bester, Johan Christiaan. 2018. Charlie Gard and the limits of the harm principle. JAMA Pediatrics 172: 300–301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 28.Feldman, Richard, and Ted A. Warfield (eds.). 2010. Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- 29.Bock, Gregory L. 2012. Making martyrs of our children: Religiously based requests in pediatrics. Ethics and Medicine 28: 89–98.Google Scholar
- 30.NeJaime, Douglas, and Reva B. Siegel. 2015. Conscience wars: Complicity-based conscience claims in religion and politics. Yale Law Journal 124: 2516–2591.Google Scholar
- 31.Wicclair, Mark R. 2011. Conscientious objection in health care: An ethical analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 32.Liberman, Alida. 2017. Wrongness, responsibility, and conscientious refusals in health care. Bioethics 31: 495–504.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 33.Schuklenk, Udo, and Ricardo Smalling. 2017. Why medical professionals have no moral claim to conscientious objection accommodation in liberal democracies. Journal of Medical Ethics 43: 234–240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 34.Engelhardt, H. Tristram, Jr. 1996. The foundations of bioethics. 2nd ed. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- 35.Mustafa, Yassar. 2014. Islam and the four principles of medical ethics. Journal of Medical Ethics 40: 479–483.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 36.Lipka, Michael. 2016. A closer look at Jehovah’s Witnesses living in the U.S. Pew Research Center, Washington, DC. http://pewrsr.ch/1T2yaLH. Accessed October 5, 2018.
- 37.Black, Cherie. 2007. Boy dies of leukemia after refusing treatment for religious reasons. Seattle Post-Intelligencer, November 28. https://www.seattlepi.com/local/article/Boy-dies-of-leukemia-after-refusing-treatment-for-1257094.php.
- 38.Roberts, Laura. 2010. Teenage Jehovah’s Witness refuses blood transfusion and dies. Daily Telegraph, May 18. https://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/health/news/7734480/Teenage-Jehovahs-Witness-refuses-blood-transfusion-and-dies.html.
- 39.Vaillant, Daniel. 2000. The prosecution of Christian Scientists: A needed protection for children or insult added to injury. Cleveland State Law Review 48: 479–502.Google Scholar
- 40.Woolley, S. 2005. Children of Jehovah’s Witnesses and adolescent Jehovah’s Witnesses: What are their rights? Archives of Disease in Childhood 90: 715–719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 41.Offit, Paul A. 2015. Bad faith: When religious belief undermines modern medicine. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
- 42.Murphy, Timothy F. 2012. In defense of irreligious bioethics. American Journal of Bioethics 12(12): 3–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 43.Orr, Robert D., and Leigh B. Genesen. 1998. Medicine, ethics and religion: Rational or irrational? Journal of Medical Ethics 24: 385–387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 44.Savulescu, Julian. 1998. Two worlds apart: Religion and ethics. Journal of Medical Ethics 24: 382–384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 45.Feinberg, Joel. 2007. The child’s right to an open future. In Philosophy of education: An anthology, ed. Randall R. Curren, 112–123. Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
- 46.Millum, Joseph. 2014. The foundation of the child’s right to an open future. Journal of Social Philosophy 45: 522–538.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 47.Sulmasy, Daniel P. 2002. Informed consent without autonomy. Fordham Urban Law Journal 30: 207–220.Google Scholar
- 48.Peppin, John F. 1997. The Christian physician in the non-Christian institution: Objections of conscience and physician value neutrality. Christian Bioethics 3: 39–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 49.Scofield, Giles R. 1993. Ethics consultation: The least dangerous profession? Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2: 417–426.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 50.MacIntyre, Alasdair C. 1984. After virtue: A study in moral theory. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
- 51.MacIntyre, Alasdair C. 1988. Whose justice? Which rationality?. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
- 52.Mackie, J.L. 1990. Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
- 53.Zaner, Richard M. 1988. Ethics and the clinical encounter. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
- 54.Arras, John. 2016. Theory and bioethics. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Winter 2016 ed, ed. Edward N. Zalta. Stanford: Stanford University Metaphysics Research Lab. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/theory-bioethics.
- 55.Engelhardt, H. Tristram, Jr. 2003. The bioethics consultant: Giving moral advice in the midst of moral controversy. HEC Forum 15: 362–382.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 56.Engelhardt, H. Tristram, Jr. 2009. Credentialing strategically ambiguous and heterogeneous social skills: The emperor without clothes. HEC Forum 21: 298–306.Google Scholar
- 57.Engelhardt, H. Tristram, Jr. 2011. Core competencies for health care ethics consultants: In search of professional status in a post-modern world. HEC Forum 23: 129–145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 58.Churchill, Larry R. 1978. The ethicist in professional education. Hastings Center Report 8(6): 13–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 59.Engelhardt, H. Tristram, Jr. 1991. Bioethics and secular humanism: The search for a common morality. Eugene: Wipf and Stock.Google Scholar
- 60.Engelhardt, H. Tristram, Jr. 2011. Confronting moral pluralism in posttraditional Western societies: Bioethics critically reassessed. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 36: 243–260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 61.Albert, Hans. 1968. Traktat über kritische Vernunft. Tübingen: Mohr.Google Scholar
- 62.Engelhardt, H. Tristram, Jr. (ed.). 2011. Bioethics critically reconsidered: Having second thoughts. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
- 63.American Society for Bioethics and Humanities. 2011. Core competencies for healthcare ethics consultation. 2nd ed. Glenview: American Society for Bioethics and Humanities.Google Scholar
- 64.Rasmussen, Lisa M. 2011. Clinical ethics consultation’s dilemma, and a solution. Journal of Clinical Ethics 22: 380–392.Google Scholar
- 65.Beauchamp, Tom L., and James F. Childress. 2013. Principles of biomedical ethics. 7th ed. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar