The Epistemic Indispensability Argument
- 26 Downloads
Abstract
This article elaborates the epistemic indispensability argument, which fully embraces the epistemic contribution of mathematics to science, but rejects the contention that such a contribution is a reason for granting reality to mathematicalia. Section 1 introduces the distinction between ontological and epistemic readings of the indispensability argument. Section 2 outlines some of the main flaws of the first premise of the ontological reading. Section 3 advances the epistemic indispensability argument in view of both applied and pure mathematics. And Sect. 4 makes a case for the epistemic approach, which firstly calls into question the appeal to inference to the best explanation in the defense of the indispensability claim; secondly, distinguishes between mathematical and physical posits; and thirdly, argues that even though some may think that inference to the best explanation works in the postulation of physical posits, no similar considerations are available for postulating mathematicalia.
Keywords
Indispensability argument Epistemic approach Mathematics Science Inference to the best explanation OntologyNotes
Acknowledgements
This article is a result of the governmental funded research Grant FONDECYT de Iniciación, No. 11160324, “The Physico-Mathematical Structure of Scientific Laws: On the Roles of Mathematics, Models, Measurements, and Metaphysics in the Construction of Laws in Physics,” CONICYT, Chile.
References
- Arabatzis, T. (2006). Representing electrons. A biographical approach to theoretical entities. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
- Azzouni, J. (1997). Thick epistemic access: Distinguishing the mathematical from the empirical. The Journal of Philosophy, 94(9), 472–484.Google Scholar
- Azzouni, J. (2004). Deflating existential consequence. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Baker, A. (2005). Are there genuine mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? Mind, 114(454), 223–238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Baker, A. (2009). Mathematical explanation in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(3), 611–633.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Baker, A., & Colyvan, M. (2011). Indexing and mathematical explanation. Philosophia Mathematica, 19(3), 323–334.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Balaguer, M. (1998). Platonism and anti-platonism in mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Bangu, S. (2008). Inference to the best explanation and mathematical realism. Synthese, 160(1), 13–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Bangu, S. (2012). The applicability of mathematics in science: Indispensability and ontology. London: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
- Bigelow, J. (1988). The reality of numbers. A physicalist’s philosophy of mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
- Bueno, O. (2005). Dirac and the dispensability of mathematics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 36(3), 465–490.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Bueno, O. (2009). Mathematical fictionalism. In O. Bueno, & O. Linnebo (Eds.), New waves in the philosophy of mathematics (pp. 59–79). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Bueno, O. (2016). An anti-realist application of the application of mathematics. Philosophical Studies, 173(10), 2591–2604. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0670-y.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Bueno, O., & Colyvan, M. (2011). An inferential conception of the application of mathematics. Nous, 45(2), 345–374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Bueno, O., & French, S. (2018). Applying mathematics: Immersion, inference, interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Clowe, D., Bradac, M., Gonzalez, A. H., Marketevich, M., Randall, S. W., & Zaritsky, D. (2006). A direct empirical proof of the existence of dark matter. The Astrophysical Journal Letters, 648(2), L109–L113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Colyvan, M. (1999). Confirmation theory and indispensability. Philosophical Studies, 96(1), 1–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Colyvan, M. (2001). The indispensability of mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Colyvan, M. (2002). Mathematics and aesthetics considerations in science. Mind, 111(441), 69–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Colyvan, M. (2006). Scientific realism and mathematical nominalism: A marriage made in hell. In C. Cheyne, & J. Worrall (Eds.), Rationality and reality: Conversations with Alan Musgrave (pp. 225–237). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Colyvan, M. (2012). An introduction to the philosophy of mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Daly, C., & Langford, S. (2009). Mathematical explanation and indispensability arguments. The Philosophical Quarterly, 59(237), 641–658.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Dyson, F. (1962). Mathematics in the physical sciences. Scientific American, 211(3), 128–146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Field, H. (1980). Science without numbers. A defence of nominalism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
- Field, H. (1989). Realism, mathematics and modality. New York: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Franklin, J. (2014). An aristotelian realist philosophy of mathematics. Mathematics as the science of quantity and structure. London: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
- Freese, K. (2006). The dark side of the universe. Nuclear Instruments and Methods in Physics Research, A, 559(2), 337–340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Lange, M. (2002). An introduction to the philosophy of physics: Locality, fields, energy, and mass. New York: Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Leng, M. (2002). What’s wrong with indispensability? (Or, the case for recreational mathematics). Synthese, 131(3), 395–417.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Leng, M. (2010). Mathematics and reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Liggins, D. (2016). Grounding and the indispensability argument. Synthese, 193(2), 531–548. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0478-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Maddy, P. (1990). Realism in mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Maddy, P. (1992). Indispensability and practice. The Journal of Philosophy, 89(6), 275–289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Maddy, P. (1995). Naturalism and ontology. Philosophia Mathematica, 3(3), 248–270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Maddy, P. (1997). Naturalism in mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Melia, J. (2000). Weaseling away the indispensability argument. Mind, 109(435), 435–479.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Melia, J. (2002). Response to Colyvan. Mind, 111(441), 75–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Morrison, M. (2015). Reconstructing reality. Models, mathematics, and simulations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Musgrave, A. (1986). Arithmetical platonism: Is Wright wrong or must Field yield? In M. Fricke (Ed.), Essays in honour of Bob Durrant (pp. 90–110). Dunedin: Otago University Philosophy Department.Google Scholar
- Panza, M., & Sereni, A. (2016). The varieties of indispensability arguments. Synthese, 193(2), 469–516. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0977-9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Pincock, C. (2012). Mathematics and scientific representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Psillos, S. (2012). Anti-nominalistic scientific realism: A defence. In A. Bird, B. Ellis, & H. Sankey (Eds.), Properties, powers, and structures. Issues in the metaphysics of realism (pp. 63–80). New York and London: Routledge.Google Scholar
- Putnam, H. (1971). Philosophy of logic. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Mathematics, matter and method: Philosophical papers (Vol. 1, pp. 323–357). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
- Quine, W. V. O. (1948). On what there is. The Review of Metaphysics, 2(5), 21–38.Google Scholar
- Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Two dogmas of empiricism. The Philosophical Review, 60(1), 20–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Quine, W. V. O. (1981). Theories and things. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Quine, W. V. O. (2004). Quintessence. In R. F. Gibson Jr. (Ed.), Basic readings from the philosophy of W. V. Quine. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Resnik, M. D. (1997). Mathematics as a science of patterns. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
- Saatsi, J. (2011). The enhanced indispensability argument: Representational versus explanatory role of mathematics in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(1), 143–154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Saatsi, J. (2016). On the ‘indiepensable explanatory role’ of mathematics. Mind, 125(500), 1045–1070.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Sober, E. (1993). Mathematics and indispensability. The Philosophical Review, 102(1), 35–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Steiner, M. (1995). The applicabilities of mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica, 3(2), 129–156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Steiner, M. (1998). The applicability of mathematics as a philosophical problem. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Tegmark, M. (2014). Our mathematical universe. My quest for the ultimate nature of reality. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
- Weinberg, S. (1993). Dreams of a final theory. London: Vintage.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Wigner, E. (1960). The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics, 13, 1–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar