Introduction

In spite of the depth of the divergence of Heidegger’s thinking from Husserl’s—which originated already during their collaborations in FreiburgFootnote 1 and only deepened from thereon—there is a theme which unites near to all philosophical efforts of both thinkers: their primal concern with the fate of western humanity. Husserl and Heidegger both operated in what is one of the most turbulent of all times western culture has had to endure. Moreover, both understood their own thinking directly in relation to an imminent crisis of the west. They both firmly believed humanity stood in need of a new spiritual orientation which the scientific developments of modernity had somehow been obstructing. Moreover, both felt that to provide such direction itself was to set on a kind of spiritual task which they had been called upon to take up.

Yet both thinkers took up this task in what prima facie appear to be very different ways. Husserl honestly considered that the transcendental phenomenology he had developed was the culmination of all the spiritual and philosophical efforts of human history (see Hua VI 13, 71). This progression of history for him was identical to the progression of reason. Transcendental phenomenology was to be the ultimate rational and therewith simultaneously the ultimate responsible philosophy. Evidently, the completion of such a trajectory ought itself to take a rational shape; it can only exist in complete transparency to itself, and thus must present itself in unambiguous terms and with demanding scientific rigor. It is from this towering viewpoint that Husserl claims to identify a threat to western society, seeks to trace its origins through modern history of science, and finally proposes a cure to it.

Heidegger understood his philosophical calling quite differently. It is often said that Heidegger was more sensitive to history, practice, and inter-subjectivity, and that the limits of reason within the bounds set by those factors was not understood by Husserl. It is hard, I think, to maintain such a view for anyone acquainted with the breadth and depth of Husserl’s thought. But at the least it seems uncontroversial that Heidegger believed Husserl’s project had to be rejected on grounds of it being an onto-theological hubris beyond the reach of mortal beings. This is hardly a signal of modesty on Heidegger’s behalf, however, who in turn claimed insight into the peculiar form of understanding shaping his time unavailable to most others.Footnote 2 This form of understanding is what he called the ‘essence’ of technology (Wesen der Technik),Footnote 3 in turn closely related to the so-called ‘essence’ of modern science (Wesen der modernen Wissenschaft).Footnote 4 For Heidegger, the threat posed by them does not lie in obfuscating the one true path of reason, but in concealing our relationship to being.

In spite of the abundance of literature on the relation between various aspects of their thinking, Heidegger’s later critique of technology and scienceFootnote 5 is still rarely studied with regard to its relation to Husserl’s critique of modern science and technological thinking. Although no sufficient reasons, this could be partially due to the lack of strong evidence that Heidegger studied Husserl’s Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften (1936)Footnote 6 or simply to the notorious difficulty of Husserl’s work generally. It may also have to do with Heidegger’s so-called Kehre,Footnote 7 which is generally seen as weakening ties to phenomenology—and thus also, it may be assumed, to Husserl’s critique of modern science. It would be contentious, however, to qualify Husserl’s historical analyses in his final work as strictly phenomenological—which means this too cannot straightforwardly dispense of the need to explore the convergence of their respective critiques of the technological-scientific worldview.

This paper seeks to explore the depth of that convergence as well as to highlight the essentially different philosophical viewpoints from which it takes place. In contra-chronological order, section two first deals with Heidegger’s critique of technology and science in his writings after the Kehre. After that, section three traces some of Heidegger’s ideas in Husserl’s interpretation developed just over 15 years earlier. In the final part, I conclude that, irrespective of the historical question whether Heidegger studied Husserl’s final work in detail, many core aspects of Heidegger’s critique can be traced back to Husserl.

Heidegger on the Technological-Scientific Worldview

Few scholars would say Heidegger’s later writings on technology are an easy read. This is particularly due to the way they are tied into his elusive philosophy of being. Indeed, the ‘essence’ of technology has ‘everything’ to do with being (FT 16). It can therefore be useful to start from a distinction made much earlier by Heidegger called the ontological difference (ontologische Differenz).Footnote 8 As Nicholson (1985) put it some 30 years ago, the ontological difference is between ‘on one side, all that exists, on the other, the very existence of what exists’ (Nicholson 1985: 357). In other words, it is the difference between what is and the being of what is; so between beings and their being.

At first sight, this may not seem to get us very far. The distinction between being and beings—traditionally understood within the dichotomy of essences or substances as abstract property-bearers and their predicables—is obviously an old one, and making it by no means solves the problem of how exactly to account for being. Traditional western philosophy has understood being both as property—a special kind of property (Aquinas, among others) or a property of concepts or propositional constructs (Frege and Russell, respectively)—and not as a property (most notably Locke and Hume; the former regarding being as substance, the latter rejecting sub-stances ‘standing under’ sensible properties). As is well known, Heidegger believed the general approach underlying all these views to be false. For him, being can be thought of neither as sub-stance accommodating properties nor as a property itself. It must, therefore, be qualified in a wholly different way, as was Heidegger’s principal concern throughout his career.

Although a somewhat blunt over-generalization, it can be helpful to distinguish two general ways in which Heidegger approached the issue of being. First, we can think of the earlier Heidegger (of Sein und Zeit) as interested particularly in what enables us (as ‘Dasein’) to relate to being. Simpler put: what sort of conditions (Existenzialen) need be in place in order for Dasein to be able to ask the question of being in the first place (SZ 11–15)?Footnote 9 This first approach, then, rather than taking the problem head on, circles it by asking for the conditions presupposed by the very question. Asking for the conditions for asking about being (a capacity most of the other animals presumably lack) allowed Heidegger to embark on a relatively systematic ‘transcendental’ (concerning conditions of possibility) task, as we find in Being and Time.

Second, the Heidegger after the Kehre can be thought of as occupied primarily with our contemporary lack of concern for being. The issue to be understood here is: how come we do not ask about being? Or put differently: why did being drift so far out of sight? And how might we ever retrieve it again more fully? Arguably, this is a more elusive concern than the earlier one, and Heidegger’s approach to it did not involve breaking it down into a network of interrelated conditions of possibility. To some extent, this absence of a quasi-analytic pursuit of various conditions of possibility explains the (yet more) cryptic flavor of the later writings.

To be sure, twentieth century philosophy did ask the question of being. It would be absurd to claim that the whole issue of being escaped notice of philosophers at any epoch of traditional philosophy from Thales up to now. But Heidegger, as everybody knows, believed they all asked the question in the wrong way. The right way of thinking about being, Heidegger thought, has drifted out of sight. Looking for the source or cause of this is precisely what brought the later Heidegger to investigate into what he called the ‘essence’ of technology.

The very question characterizing the later work—why being allegedly does not show itself to us today as a concern for thinking—nicely points us to the idea that there are different ways in which things can show up for us, including indeed being itself. This idea of a way in which things appear or are disclosed (Weise des Entbergens) in fact marks the core of Heidegger’s later thoughts about being and technology.Footnote 10 To understand this, we may start with something we can all readily observe: that the very same things can appear quite differently to different people. If, for instance, I am familiar with a certain song played on the radio, and you are not, then the song is bound to appear differently to you than to me. Likewise, we can imagine people from different cultures perceive the same objects differently. This need not necessarily be a matter of plain recognition. Standing at proximal distance to an acquaintance can be comfortable for one person and less so for another—yet neither is here at failure of recognizing any particular thing. We can explain such and other cases by saying that people have different background understandings or, to use phenomenological jargon, to say that they stand in different cultural horizons. It is due to our standing in complexly shaped cultural horizons that we are able to see the same things, yet see them in surprisingly different ways.

Dreyfus (1993), in an attempt to simplify matters, connects Heidegger’s later concerns about being to such background understandings shaped by largely implicit cultural norms and practices. Dreyfus suggests the distinction between things appearing and the way they appear matches well Heidegger’s differentiation of beings and being.Footnote 11 What explicitly comes to view in experience is, very generally speaking, things. What does not really come to view yet is tied inherently to the appearing of things is the implicit horizontal understanding within which those things doom up. Now these two sides are of course never entirely distinct. In fact there exist no ‘bare things’ which stand out of a cultural horizon in utter indifference to that horizon.Footnote 12 Not only is everything caught up in a culturally and historically shaped way of appearing. Moreover, Heidegger thinks things are also intrinsically shaped by that horizon, that is: they are determined in their very thingness by the elusive operations of cultural background forces. In other words, even the idea of a ‘bare thing’ universally understood is really only part of a culturally shaped horizon.

We can come a long way when we interpret ‘being’ for Heidegger as the implicit background structure set by cultural practice and historical situatedness. Since, as we have just seen, the being of things—so the implicit way they appear—is not radically distinct from those things but intrinsically determines them in their manner of appearing, both are always necessarily in some way co-given. In other words, wherever there are things, being co-appears (i.e., things cannot but be within and shaped by a cultural world-horizon). Now, given the great variations between cultures and ages, we can imagine one epoch of history having a closer ‘relation to being’ than others. This relation to being amounts plainly to the awareness of the necessary co-givenness of being. Put the other way around, a close relation to being would mean having an implicit understanding that things are not just things. A contrasting case is then also conceivable, namely one in which a background understanding would prevail whose interpretative scheme is so forcefully dominant that all concerns about being seem senseless. In such a particular day and age, the only things that would be granted important and real would be plain things.

This is, in essence, Heidegger’s critique of technology. It is a criticism of what I just called the ‘interpretative scheme’ which prevails in modern western culture. According to Heidegger, things show up for us in a particular way which was unknown to most previous generations of people. The same things can appear to us and to people of past ages, but the ways in which they do so can be different. To us alone do they appear through the lens of technology. With the term ‘technology,’ Heidegger does not mean plain tools or instruments but rather a very general and implicit way in which things presumably appear. He calls this peculiar scheme the ‘essence’ of technology to contrast it with technology in the mundane ‘anthropological’ sense of any particular group of things or characteristic thereof.Footnote 13 The ‘essence’ of technology, then, does not point to any instance of technological manipulation, but to a very general horizon of understanding which has come to prevail and which forces itself on all things, our interactions with them, and our thinking about them.

Most of the other important concepts the later Heidegger develops in his writings on technology—most notably ‘enframing’ (Ge-stell), ‘standing-reserve’ (Bestand), ‘destiny’ (Geschick), and ‘challenging-forth’ (herausfordern)—can be explained on the basis developed so far. First, by ‘enframing,’ Heidegger means precisely that interpretative scheme or frame shaped by the essence of technology. It thus captures the general way things are manifest.Footnote 14 Closely related, ‘standing-reserve’ denotes a central characteristic of such manner of appearing of things in our contemporary technological enframing, namely their standing ready for use, for exploitation (FT 20). The world now appears as a collection of objects on standing-reserve; they are plain things at our service; technological opportunity.

Third, to understand the rather idiosyncratic idea of ‘destiny,’ we need to take note that no interpretative scheme is a purely subjective matter. It is shaped by cultural and historical forces that lie beyond the power of the individual. Any culture is therefore destined to look at the world in a certain way, in other words, to have their distinctive way of letting things appear. This way itself can be either heeded carefully or altogether taken for granted and ignored. In neither case, however, can it be controlled freely, which means man’s ‘relation to being’ (to the way things present themselves) is to a large extent an inevitable fate.Footnote 15 This, of course, restrains Heidegger’s space to construe a solution to the problem of technological enframing, which will concern us later.

Lastly, the ‘essence’ of technology, as a way of appearing, is also characterized by Heidegger in terms of a ‘challenging’. This concept is closely related to the concept of standing-reserve. The fact of things appearing as standing-reserve makes that it becomes easy for us to use and exploit things in ways which could be said to ‘challenge’ their natural mode of presenting. Technology, so to say, levels them out; it puts all things on a par as exploitable resources. For example, instead of this patch of land calling out to be used for this kind of harvest and the other for another due to their natural characteristics, the land now appears everywhere as something to be challenged in order to make it serve whatever function forced upon it (FT 17–19). To give another example, in other ages, Heidegger thinks, a silver chalice was not like a plastic cup made just in order to drink from it. It was rather, Heidegger claims, that to be drank from. In other words, the silver resource was not ‘challenged’ when it became molded into a cup; it rather held that potential naturally within the larger cultural scheme of things. The plastic of today’s disposable coffee cup, on the other hand, would be the product of a different kind of attitude toward the natural world and our own place therein, which reflects the kind of standing-reserve use-and-dispose-of attitude of contemporary western civilization.

Much of Heidegger’s thinking about enframing after the Kehre proceeds through rather eccentric philosophical–etymological reflections. Heidegger believed that by analyzing the changes language undergoes over time he could reveal something of the shifts in the tacit background understandings that prevailed. For one, he famously claimed that technē for the Greeks did not involve the kind of challenging-manipulating of things as it does for us. A different interpretative frame ostensibly ruled here. According to Heidegger, the Greek technē did not signify a challenging but rather a ‘bringing-forth’ (Her-vor-bringen) (FT 17–18). Technique was not merely an exploitation of things to a certain end—as would be our contemporary way of technological disclosure (herausfordernde Entbergen), but instead more akin to a kind of creatively allowing something to reveal itself. Instrumental praxis here still held a certain connection to the beautiful (FT 38). This is why, Heidegger suggests, technē for the Greeks included not just technology but likewise the arts. Art was not a part of technē because art was technological in our contemporary sense, but precisely because technology itself was a creative bringing-forth just as art is.

In another one of his philosophical–etymological inquiries, Heidegger claims that the technological way of relating to things (in terms of challenging and standing-reserve) can be traced back specifically to the advent of early modern science.Footnote 16 It is not, however, as one might expect, modern science which steered the course of this development. Instead, Heidegger suggests, it is because the technological enframing became dominant that exact science was called forth. This seems to make exact science derived from the ‘essence’ of technology, rather than technology being some form of applied science as most are now probably prone to understand it. It seems it could easily be argued against this, however, that the concept of an ‘essence’ of technology thus drastically inflates; it would have prevailed already before modern science and therewith also before the technological revolutions of the renaissance (see also Wheeler 2011). At other points, Heidegger casts doubts again on this reading, noting that the ‘essence’ of technology did not ‘hold sway already’ in early modernity, but rather something closer to an omen (Vorbote) of that made its appearance here (FT 25).Footnote 17

The relation between modern science and technology becomes somewhat clearer if we consider Heidegger etymological interpretations of the concepts of ‘reality’ (Wirkliche) and ‘theory’ (Theorie) (WB 47–53). Regarding the first, Heidegger mainly focuses on showing somewhat uncontroversially that the kind of enframing in Greek academic life did not let ‘reality’ appear as exhaustible in terms of effects and consequences (causa efficiens) (WB 47–48). Regarding the second, he claims that the Greeks did not entertain the kind of objectifying attitude known to moderns which assesses the ‘real’ as something independently standing over-against (Gegenständlich). According to Heidegger, in seeking to take this kind of objective, non-interfering stance vis-à-vis reality, the moderns actually conceal a fundamental part of reality. Their disinterested outlook is not the non-doing they think it is, but a powerful attitude of challenging-forth (herausfordern) (WB 49–53). Science, then, acts on reality, and over a long period of time shapes the way all things appear, thereby excluding alternative ways of appearing. The analyses of ‘reality’ and ‘theory’ thus lead to the same conclusion the critique of technology yielded, namely that our contemporary enframing shallow thinking about important questions concerning ontology in a way ultimately beyond our free control.

Heidegger’s critiques of technology and of science therefore interlace.Footnote 18 In fact, technological instrumentality is linked closely to the prevalence of the causa efficiens with the advent of modern science (FT 11–14); the former is even said to subsist in or to be grounded in the causal (beruht im Kausalen). Heidegger further relates the concepts of enframing, challenging, and ordering that belong to the ‘essence’ of technology directly to causality, objectivity, and mathematical-exact determination as traits of the ‘essence’ of modern science (WB 53–58). It is, then, not just technology, but the combination of the ‘essences’ of technology and science which constitutes the imminent threat (Gefahr).

For Heidegger, this threat seems in the end to be almost exclusively ontological; it is the threat of an utter oblivion to the way of appearing itself, i.e., to being. In a sense, the way of appearing which prevails—as things on standing-reserve awaiting our challenging use and as nothing more than causal events in a spatiotemporal order—covers itself over.Footnote 19 The technological enframing ‘hides not only a former way of appearing as bringing-forth, but moreover hides the appearing as such’ (FT 31).Footnote 20 More simply put, Heidegger believed it prevents us from seeing that what appears to us as ‘real’ is only an interpretative scheme. It does not hold the truth about things, but rather conceals the final truth understood as the event (Ereignis) of the openness of things within a culturally determined world-horizon.

Ultimately, Heidegger does not offer any concrete cure to the problem of technology and science as interpretative frame. Its forces are not alterable by the efforts of any individual. New roads or possibly old onesFootnote 21 might open themselves in the future if we pay sufficient heed to the problem. The sciences themselves, Heidegger contends, are too segregated to offer solutions; they are confined to their restricted fields of inquiry beyond which they may not ask (WB 49–58). As the German idealists of the early nineteenth century, Heidegger alludes to art as a place to look for new possible ways of things showing themselves, but does not elaborate the point further (FT 36).

It remains at this point an open question how Heidegger thinks he has justified his preference for one scheme over another. For one, it seems it could easily be argued that the plastic cup discussed earlier also fits neatly within its scheme of practices and ways of appearing. If indeed so, then what enables Heidegger to reject it? What warrants the apparent conservative appeal to the pre-technological/scientific horizon as the preferable one? Why exactly is the technological-scientific worldview considered a threat?

Part of an answer, as was mentioned already, is that Heidegger thinks the technological scheme prevents all things from expressing something like their own unique character (see also Lovitt 1977: xxviii–xxix). Since their relation to us is universalized as a relation of standing-reserve,Footnote 22 we allegedly challenge things rather than allowing them to express themselves—as the examples of the silver of the chalice and the different patches of land illustrate. Second, and this is another side of the same coin, Heidegger thinks the technological-scientific scheme effectively conceals our relation to being. We now only see a totality of things ready at our disposal, and since being is not a thing, the very necessity of thinking about being over against beings is concealed. As W. Lovitt aptly puts it, technology is ‘the thinking that degrades Being’ (1977: xxxii)—and being is what thinking is all about for Heidegger.

One could, of course, ask for a still deeper justification. Why do we need to let things show something like their own character and why do we need a relationship to being above anything else? Unlike his former master Husserl, Heidegger does not uphold the ideal of a perfectly rational-responsible community which would allow all things to express their own essence as phenomenology exposes them. For Husserl, for instance, ‘material thing’ is an ‘essence’ (an essential way of possible object-presentation for consciousness), and hence also one or more sciences targeting that ‘region’ are required by a responsible community of people. The same goes for ‘consciousness’ or ‘numbers’; these too are essential ways of object-presentation which, by essence differing from material thingness, require their respective sciences. Husserl can thus warrant the need of essence expression and correlatively can justify criticisms of essence concealments by the normative ideal of a perfectly rational community. Heidegger, on the other hand, thinks the classic philosophical trajectory guided by reason has definitively become inaccessible to modern humanity, and so seems barred from that justificatory route.Footnote 23

Ultimately, Heidegger’s critique of the technological-scientific worldview does not appear to involve any arguments for the primacy of our relation to being. It nonetheless seems to presuppose them, since the concealment of that relation is defined as this worldview’s principal shortcoming. To be sure, Heidegger elaborated on the importance of the question of being substantially in earlier works. Discussing this would, however, take us too far beyond our current concerns.

Husserl on the Technological-Scientific Worldview

Whereas Heidegger distinguished between an ‘essence’ of technology and a closely related ‘essence’ of science, Husserl’s interpretation of the crisis facing western civilization in the 1936-work Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften limits its focus mostly on the development of what he calls the modern ‘idea’ of science (Idee der Wissenschaft) from the Renaissance onwards (Hua VI 3). The crisis, as Husserl understands it, is present in his day yet still ‘rapidly growing’ (Hua VI 14). While there certainly are crises unfolding within the foundations of various sciences, including the formal or exact disciplines, the crisis Husserl has in mind is not one about science. It rather concerns the spiritual foundations of western culture. The reason Husserl focuses predominantly on the idea of modern science nonetheless is that he believes it above everything else has come to shape the way things appear to us, to the extent that it has ‘controlled all development of world-considerations until the present day’ (Hua VI 54).Footnote 24

Husserl, then, like Heidegger, is well aware that things are seen and interpreted differently by people over different times. He is, in fact, undoubtedly more sensitive to detail in his philosophical–historical reflections than Heidegger. Unlike the rather broad and opaque accounts of ‘essences’ developed by Heidegger, Husserl takes painstaking effort to explain what he means by the idea of science and follows its development through modernity in considerable detail. Yet, much like Heidegger, he understands this idea not as an explicitly articulated one but as governed by unarticulated drives or forces (Triebkräften).Footnote 25 In a way reminding of Heidegger’s talk of destiny, Husserl notes that a tacit yet powerful ‘direction of will’ pervades and governs us (hindurchgehende Willensrichtung). The philosophical–historical enterprise of Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften therefore requires a peculiar breaking of the ‘crust’ of the surface of historical events in order to uncover a deeper meaning which did not explicitly surface at the time.Footnote 26 Although a continuous matter of debate, these historical inquiries are most likely not to be considered phenomenological investigations.Footnote 27 They are better understood as forming a philosophical–historical introduction to phenomenology.Footnote 28

Again in accordance with Heidegger, Husserl speaks of the modern idea of science as one which aims at ‘controlling’ (beherrschen) the ‘totality of things generally’ (Allheit des überhaupt Seienden). Moreover, it is said the modern scientific image gradually gained a certain control over people, shaping the sorts of questions people feel warranted in asking. Mere sciences of fact, Husserl notes, also make people of facts.Footnote 29 In particular the ‘positivistic shrinking of the idea of science’ (Hua VI 5) which Husserl sees developing in the second half of the nineteenth century ended up barring us from asking important questions.Footnote 30 These include ‘questions of humanity’ (Menschheitsfragen)—among others existential-ontological ones pertaining to the meaning of being or human existenceFootnote 31—but also metaphysical or philosophical questions (Hua VI 8), understood generally as those which transcend the world conceived of as universe of mere facts.Footnote 32 The positivism which is the outgrowth of the development of modern science ‘decapitates’ philosophy (Hua VI 7); it ‘threatens to consume’ it (Hua V 13). The current inability to ask such questions is essential to Husserl’s take on the crisis; they are what previously animated scientific inquiry, no matter how tacitly, thereby providing an overall sense of direction and a kind of positive spirit or ‘swing’ (Schwung) to their progressions (Hua VI 7).

The structure of Husserl’s diagnosis of the crisis can be summarized as follows. In brief, while the institution of the modern idea of science in the Renaissance made possible the new positivistic sciences, the latter have come to control the spirit of contemporary European humanityFootnote 33 in general (Geistes des neuzeitlichen europäischen Menschentums überhaupt) (Hua VI 59). This means Husserl focuses on the historical development of the idea of modern science and its positivistic outgrowth in order to elucidate the meaning of the crisis, which in turn is a crisis of spirit rather than of science. Exactly as Heidegger suggested some 15 years later, Husserl notes that the sciences, because they are locked within their own regional domains, are unable to address concerns of spiritual humanity (Hua VI 4). More crucially still, Husserl thinks they in fact expel them from any possible legitimate form of understanding (Hua VI 5). In other words, the crisis is essentially the holding sway of a certain frame of understanding, historically determined through the idea of modern science, which makes all questions transcending mere facts nonsensical—the same questions which (ironically) once motivated the modern idea of science.

The threat Husserl sees western society faced with thus shares with Heidegger’s critique a chief concern for the need for fundamental questioning. But for Heidegger, as we saw previously, the diagnosis and cure were cashed out almost exclusively in ontological terms. His critiques of technology and science said nothing about reason, human responsibility, justice, and so forth; they pertained to our ‘relation to being’ only. This contrasts in complicated ways with Husserl, for whom the importance of philosophical questions has everything to do with reason, truth, and ethical responsibility.Footnote 34 Husserl does not merely highlight the necessity of a ‘questioning thinking’ (to borrow a phrase from Heidegger), he also provides detailed answers in other writings based on his own conception of transcendental phenomenology. Before turning to that, however, the diagnosis of the crisis through the idea of science needs to be clarified further here.

Husserl traces the idea of modern science back to the Renaissance, at first in particular to Galilei.Footnote 35 The unique impulse Renaissance philosophy gave to western civilization, he claims, rests on the institution of a simple but revolutionary double idea (Hua VI 5 19–20). It is the invention of a new way of conceiving of the world we live in as one consisting of a totality of things forming a single rational unity,Footnote 36 and more specifically, a rational unity that is controllable in its entire determinable being through one universal mathematical science.Footnote 37 Thus Husserl’s quest at first becomes to show how mathematics is employed and conceived of in relation to the study of nature, which he traces from Galilei and Descartes through to Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, Berkeley, and finally to Kant (Hua VI 20–104).

The theme of Husserl’s investigation, however, is not the content matter of mathematics itself, but the development of the tacitly operative idea of modern science as a universal mathematical science of nature. Husserl does not lump centuries of developments into one idea of technological or scientific conceiving, but carefully treats different thinkers and the mark they left on the contemporary scientific worldview separately. Yet again in a vocabulary reminding of the later Heidegger, he speaks of the great philosophers of modern science as ‘concealing and unconcealing’ (entdeckender und verdeckender) geniuses (Hua VI 53). Especially when their ideas are taken over by next generations, tacit ‘shifts in meaning’ (Sinnverschiebungen) take place (Hua VI 46). Just as Heidegger analyzed words to reveal shifts in background understandings, Husserl claims that what superficially appears to be one scientific enterprise can acquire a different meaning over time. It is contextualized differently; set within a changed horizon of sense (verwandelten Sinneshorizont) (Hua VI 48), with the original thinking (ursprüngliches Denken) being tacitly covered over.

This process, according to Husserl, makes it possible for science ultimately to become mere technē.Footnote 38 In fact, as Husserl further remarks, the threat of science becoming mere technē is inherent to the very essence of the new science. Nature can be controlled by the new mathematical science only through a ‘meaning-emptied technical thinking’ (sinnesentleertes technisches Denken) (Hua VI 57). This emptying of meaning is simply a necessary consequence of its thoroughly formalized method. The increasing formalization of exact natural science is simultaneously a concealing of the original meaning which the scientist, ‘in the best case a brilliant technician in the respective method,’ is generally not capable of retrieving.Footnote 39 To lay bare the development of the changing sense of the idea of modern science thus calls for a new kind of historical and responsible critique beyond the scopes of the sciences—which is the partial aim of Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften.Footnote 40

Originally, Husserl notes, the modern idea of a universal mathematical science of nature had its roots in the practical measuring activities of the pre-scientifically experienced surrounding world (vorwissenschaftlich-anschaulichen Umwelt) (Hua VI 24). The things of the experienced surrounding world already have their own ‘habits’ and ‘typicalities’; their typical ways of appearing and relating to each other (Hua VI 28). This goes for their shapes, qualities, patterns of behavior, interactions, and so on. Phenomenologically speaking, to perceive is always to have something given in a pattern of future directed expectations; it involves complex ‘predictions’ of future occurrences, although these predictions are of a distinctively passive kind. However, things do not for that reason appear as structured according to absolute laws. The very idea that all things would stand under such laws naturally has no place in pre-scientific experience at all.

The great event of modern science, according to Husserl, is that it conceives for the first time of that idea; that the endless field of experienced objects with their pre-given typicalities and habits is determinable through its approximation to ideal systems in a way universally accessible to anyone. The Greeks, Husserl thinks, lacked that idea. To be sure, they had mathematical systems, and these were at various instances applied to nature. Yet Husserl maintains that the relation of pure mathematics to the world of everyday experience was here framed differently. Natural science in the modern sense is not just mathematics occasionally applied to nature. It is a distinctive idea, which later becomes an implicit interpretative scheme, namely that the totality of endlessly experienceable nature can be made to fit in ever-increasing exactitude universally valid mathematical systems. It is only relative to that idea that the geometries of the Greeks can be contrasted as being ‘world-estranged’ (weltentfremdete ideale Geometrie) (Hua VI 31).

Importantly, this idea is not immediately conceived of with regard to the totality of worldly beings. At first, it is applied to the spatiotemporal manifold only. The new science of nature initially manages to establish exact results solely in regard of shapes (Gestaltenmathematik). This is ultimately due to the fact that, phenomenologically speaking, pre-scientific experience constitutes all things with extension for all of us (Hua VI 30). Yet, Husserl notes, the question soon arises whether something similar could not also hold for the concrete world in all its conceivable determinations.Footnote 41 That is to say, that a mathematical index could hold for any possible determination of res extensa; for color, sound, warmth, and so on (Hua VI 35). This idea, Husserl claims, while today treated as ‘unquestionably obvious’ (fraglose Selbstverständlichkeit) (Hua VI 35), was not yet wholly transparent to Galilei who first instituted the modern idea of science.

Thus, Husserl suggests, the idea of a mathesis universalis in Leibnizian fashion came to be conceived; a single universal science for the totality of beings in all their natural-objective determinations. The obvious problem this new idea faces is, however, that it is unclear how the ‘sensible qualities’ (sinnliche Qualitäten) of the objects of the experienced surrounding world could approximate an ideally constructed index in the same direct manner as their extension can (Hua VI 31–32). Colors, sounds, temperatures, and so on, are not like spatiality measurable directly in relation to any mathematical system accessible to all which they can approximate in increasing exactitude (Hua VI 32–33).Footnote 42 This, too, of course, has its particular phenomenological foundations, but that lies beyond the scope of the historical-introductory function of Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften.

The very problem of the mathematizability of sensible qualities is absolutely central to Husserl’s tracing of the roots of the crisis. Husserl thinks this problem, which is originally of a theoretical-methodological nature and furthermore wholly indebted to the guiding ideal of a single universal science of the totality of nature, undergoes peculiar shifts of sense over time; it becomes appropriated ontologically and epistemologically. In short, Husserl believes the theoretical problem of the exact determination of extra-spatiotemporal features reifies the idea that through all changes in subjective apprehension there is given one true world, namely that world which is universally knowable in mathematical exactitude by abstracting from all supposedly merely subjective-contingent qualities (Hua VI 32). In other words, since extra-spatiotemporal features of objects cannot be directly correlated to ideal poles of pure mathematical systems, they are no longer considered part of the real. The limited scope of possible success of the modern scientific method thus leads to a confusion of the restrains of method for the actual object under scrutiny. It is a case of the concept or method become reality.Footnote 43

This is, in brief, the first important change of sense which the modern idea of science made possible. It is, Husserl thinks, the break of the original unity of the human–world relation in pre-scientific world-experience into an ‘objective’ and a ‘subjective’ part as a result of the problem of bringing extra-spatiotemporal features—not only sensory qualities but also all cultural productions (Kultureigenschaften) and ultimately the psyche or consciousness itself—in direct correspondence to a mathematical index. This is cashed out, roughly speaking, first in the distinction between primary and secondary qualities for the empiricists and later between pure and empirical concepts for Kant. This way, the new science first brings with it a ‘complete metamorphosis of the idea of world in general’ (Hua VI 61).Footnote 44 The original unity of the human–world relation is overlaid by a theoretical distinction which shapes and constrains what we think of as real.

The second, related consequence that is of perhaps even greater importance to Husserl is the likewise ‘now obvious’ distinction which has come to prevail between a priori mathematical-ideal and a posteriori natural-scientific knowledge. According to Husserl, the successes of pure mathematics and the a priori certainty of its results contrast with the laws of nature which, although thoroughly mathematical themselves, are considered a posteriori for being only inductively accessible and derived from factual experiences. The two kinds of knowledge seem to oppose each other naturally: a priori mathematics of ideal space and time, and—although employing a priori mathematics—impure natural science (Hua VI 55–56). It is on grounds of this conception that Kant develops the early modern ontology of primary and secondary qualities in epistemological terms. That is to say, we find the same underlying thought now expressed in terms of our mind’s access to the world. It leads to the idea that while we allegedly possess an ‘inborn’ capacity for a priori insight in mathematics concerning space and time, we have no such a priori evidences regarding anything that involves any concrete worldly content because of our inductive access to all laws governing that. This conception, therefore, still cannot unify the human–world relation because the notion of a priori gets wrongly restricted solely to mathematics.Footnote 45

In short, then, Husserl believed the successes of modern mathematical natural science led to the reconceptualization of the human–world relation as divided into subjective (‘illusory’) sensory fillings of objects and objective (‘real’) spatiotemporal determinations, while dividing the cognitive faculty in a posteriori knowledge about nature and a priori knowledge exclusively concerning the mathematics of space and time. Kant’s transcendental theory is thus deemed no exception to the ruling paradigm. For Husserl, it rather rephrases the same idea in transcendental-epistemological terms, qualifying on supposedly a priori grounds (through a transcendental examination of a priori ‘inborn’ forms) as unscientific all propositions not construed out of the a priori spatiotemporal manifold.

Simultaneously, Husserl notes, great problems for the development of a rational psychology—in other words, for a mathematical index for the study of subjective consciousness—are brought into the horizon of the modern idea of science.Footnote 46 Guided by the ideal of one universal science of objective nature, the psyche too is enframed as an object in the causal world order. But this problem, although leading to the allegedly flawed naturalist epistemologies of in particular Locke and Hume, simultaneously makes something good possible. Specifically under the unprecedented severity of the Humean threat of skepticism the advent of an alternative, indeed contrary, philosophical worldview is brought into being, namely that of transcendental philosophy (Hua VI 70–71).

As Husserl develops in many of his works, the naturalistic-positivistic sciences, here understood as the outcome of the modern idea of an all-encompassing mathematical natural science, depart from a naïve acceptance of a world of self-existing objects.Footnote 47 According to Husserl, in a completely evolved philosophical naturalism, reason starts and terminates with those self-existing objects.Footnote 48 Beyond them, there are no longer meaningful questions possible. Transcendentalism, on the other hand, says that the sense of independent being the world of natural science has just is an accomplishment of subjective experience.Footnote 49 Thus, instead of starting with the object and from there running against the wall of subjectivity, it starts with the latter and appropriates the objective world rightly as a sense-accomplishment of subjective experience. Naturalism, as Husserl maintained from very early on, shall in fact never be able to describe the subjective life of consciousness in mathematical exactitude. Even if perfect mathematical indices would be developed, the results would inevitably yield mere correlations (see, especially, Hua V 16–19). They would bypass the essence of consciousness itself, which Husserl thinks is inherently non-spatial—much like the idealities of mathematics are not anywhere in three-dimensional space.

The rest of the history of philosophy after Kant, Husserl notes, can be characterized as a battle between naturalism and transcendentalism (Hua VI 71). The first movement finally strands in the positivistic sciences; the other terminates in transcendental phenomenology. One is responsible for the crisis; the other the solution to it. Scientific positivism, starting and terminating with objects, cannot explain but estranges from consciousness, ideal laws, and indeed all fundamental philosophical concerns—particularly the ‘mystery of all mysteries’ (Rätsel aller Rätsel): the essential correlation of ‘thinking and being’ (Vernunft und Seiendem überhaupt), of subjectivity and objectivity (Hua VI 12). Which one wins the battle, as Husserl puts it somewhat dramatically, is to determine whether the European spirit is reborn out of true philosophy or whether the crisis means the downfall of western civilization.Footnote 50

At this point it would be fair to ask, as we did with Heidegger, what justifies Husserl’s negative evaluation of the development of the idea of modern science. Here, however, the answer seems to be quite simple: for Husserl modern science plainly ended up getting things wrong. It misconstrues the way the human–world relation is essentially constituted while further preventing us from asking deeper questions about that, thereby (as Heidegger also said) peculiarly reifying its own flawed perspective. This is surely not to say that Husserl is against the natural sciences as such. He only criticizes the scientific worldview as the dominant way of conceiving of reality, insofar as it is an irrational and therefore irresponsible worldview.

This leaves it open, of course, how exactly Husserl warrants the claim that it is wrong. In this respect, Husserl’s critique is, as Heidegger’s, tied cohesively into the rest of his philosophy. Its justification ultimately depends on his account of transcendental phenomenology as the professed true end-form (Endstiftung) of the development of the idea of modern science. While addressing that obviously lies beyond the scope of this paper, it is worth considering some important aspects briefly to shed light on the viewpoint from which Husserl criticizes the technological-scientific outlook.

In contradistinction to Heidegger’s, Husserl’s critique is driven by the pursuit of pure reason and pure human responsibility through the development of a universal first philosophy. Husserl’s idea of a first philosophy is that of a systematic, ideal and thereby universally shareable system which is capable of clarifying the final sense of the human–world relation in all its essential aspects. The validity of its propositions must further be based on indubitable (a priori) evidence. This task, the details of which are not addressed in Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften but in other works, presupposes an absolutely certain beginning. As is well known, Husserl claims to have found this in the so-called a priori correlation of subject and object (Hua VI 161). The a priori correlation, the proof of which is intricate and continuously revisited by Husserl, states that there can be no object without consciousness.Footnote 51 Even the idea of an object or world independently of consciousness requires a consciousness entertaining the idea; it too is a sense accomplished by a consciousness. Without dwelling on the details, the task of phenomenology then is to take that correlation seriously and to study all the essential structures of all conceivable subject–object relations precisely as they are manifest.

In Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften, the unity of the human–world relation is cashed out not in terms of intentionality (as in Ideas I from 1913), but through the concept of ‘lifeworld’ (Lebenswelt): the ‘continuously as-real given world experienced in our concrete world-life’.Footnote 52 The lifeworld, a richly multi-faceted but also relatively elusive concept,Footnote 53 denotes something like the everyday world of human praxis. It is not the ultimate ground of all world-constitution, but rather points to the default place human beings have in the world. Even the natural scientist is ultimately a human being living in the experienced everyday world (in dieser Welt lebende Mensch), and the questions she asks can never pertain to more than the world of real and possible experiences (wirklicher und möglicher Erfahrungsphänomene) (Hua VI 50). Yet the lifeworld is at risk of being forgotten by the positivistic sciences which reduce the world to a mind-independent collection of facts.

Although sometimes taken so, the lifeworld does not seem to be the focal point of Husserl’s Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften. It is one of many things whose true essence is neglected by fact-oriented science, next to among others subjectivity itself, ideal laws, the subject-world correlation, and moral values—none of which exist in the stricter naturalistic sense. Ultimately, all these problems—which Husserl thinks are unsolvable from a naturalist viewpoint—point to transcendental phenomenology as the ultimate responsible philosophy which, unlike the naturalist worldview which has come to rule, can accommodate in scientific rigor the being of anything just as it presents itself, prior to overlaying it with a technological-scientific scheme which would prevent them from expressing their true essence.

Carr (1974) and Moran (2012) both suggested that Husserl vastly over-estimated the potential of transcendental phenomenology by positing it as cure for the crisis. Admittedly, it is hard to imagine how the phenomenological science we know from Husserl’s collections of manuscripts could save western civilization. Yet to focus on those meticulous phenomenological analyses would be, I would argue, to miss the crux of his criticism. The crisis, for Husserl, as for Heidegger, is about a certain way of framing things. This way of framing, Husserl maintained, cloaks the true essence of certain things and estranges us from deeper inquiries.Footnote 54 For Husserl as perhaps for any honest philosopher, the only way to responsibly disprove this frame and to open a new road beyond it would be to show that it is incorrect and to provide a better alternative. Thus considered, there can be no responsible solution to the crisis other than of the kind Husserl sought to offer: that of a new, rational, and thoroughly transparent philosophy.

Conclusion

The extent to which Husserl and Heidegger oppose each other with regard to what they take to be genuine philosophy profoundly marks their different solutions to the crisis resulting from the technological-scientific worldview. For Husserl, philosophy equals responsibility—which can only be achieved through reason—and as such it is both an inherently rational as well as an ethical enterprise. It demands loyalty to the things themselves, involves rigor and precision to maintain a character of universality, and requests an unconditional will to determine life individually and socially in accordance with laws of reason. For Heidegger, by contrast, the solution to the crisis is no longer deemed to lie in the hands of the rational philosopher—hence the famous remark that at this point in time ‘only a God can save us’ (nur ein Gott kann uns retten).Footnote 55 Philosophy should instead move to a questioning and heedful thinking about being in the most general of terms.

Within this archetypical opposition, however, we found a deeper convergence of ideas regarding technological-scientific enframing. This holds for certain methodical principles of their respective inquiries—such as the idea that we view things differently over time, that we have limited control over this, and that we are capable of tracing shifts in background understandings through special historical analysis. But it also holds for the content of their criticisms. Both philosophers identify a threat in the way science and technology yield a meaning-emptied technical thinking. For both, the problem lies not in science or in technology itself, but in how they have tacitly come to shape our sense of the real and the sorts of questions we feel warranted in asking. For Heidegger as for Husserl, genuine, non-technical, philosophical thinking can be a matter neither of mere logical inference nor of plain empirical facts.Footnote 56 Philosophy must go beyond the sciences in order to provide a meaning which they themselves must methodically exclude.

Notwithstanding these deeper similarities between Heidegger’s critique of the technological-scientific worldview and Husserl’s some 15 years earlier, one cannot avoid the impression that at least in terms of detail of historical-exegetic analysis Husserl’s exposition significantly surpasses Heidegger’s. Heidegger’s thought on the technological-scientific worldview does not pursue exactitude like Husserl’s. Central notions such as the ‘essence’ of technology and of science arguably remain underdeveloped; they are supposed to cover centuries of modern history, their precise signification as well as exact historical origin being up to the reader’s guess. Ultimately, in the light of its contrast to Husserl’s discussion, this could lead one to wonder what substantial theoretical contributions Heidegger’s historically influential work on technology really makes. Although potentially unsatisfactory, one possible (and charitable) response to this would once more point to Heidegger’s original departure from Husserl regarding what makes a genuine philosopher. The philosopher—for Heidegger a heeder of being, a task beyond calculative precision, rational systematicity, and the pursuit of reason; for Husserl the ‘true rationalist,’Footnote 57 the ‘real positivist,’Footnote 58 the ‘strongest realist,’Footnote 59 indeed, the transcendental idealist.