Advertisement

Inverse Problems

  • Mario BungeEmail author
Article
  • 19 Downloads

Abstract

Although to live is to face problems, the general concept of a problem has been significantly understudied. So much so, that the publication of Polya’s delightful How to Solve It (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1945) caused quite a stir. And, although the concept of a conceptual problem is philosophical because it is deep and occurs across fields, from mathematics to politics, no philosophers have produced any memorable studies of it. Moreover, the word ‘problem’ is absent from most philosophical reference works. There are plenty of texts on particular problems such as those of evil and induction, but none on the general concept of a conceptual problem—as if it were not a problematic concept. Worse, we are seldom told that doing original mathematics, science or technology is to wrestle with original problems. Nor have we been told that the hardest problems are likely to be inverse, in that they go from effect to cause, or from sketch to implementation, or from conclusion to premises—as in diagnosing disease from symptoms, looking for a westward passage from Europe to Asia, and designing public policies to attack social issues. The existence of this significant gap in the philosophical literature justifies the publication of the present study.

Keywords

Problem Inverse problem Causation Presupposition Problem generator Solution 

Notes

References

  1. Asimov, I. (1981). The role of the heretic. In D. Goldsmith (Ed.), Scientists confront Velikovsky. New York: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar
  2. Bunge, M. (1945). Neutron–proton scattering at 8.8 and 13 MeV. Nature, 156, 301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bunge, M. (1959a). Causality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Bunge, M. (1959b). ¿Qué es un problema científico? Holmbergia (Buenos Aires) VI, 15, 47–63.Google Scholar
  5. Bunge, M. (1967). Scientific research, chapter 1. Berlin, NY: Springer.Google Scholar
  6. Bunge, M. (1998). Scientific research (2nd ed.). New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.Google Scholar
  7. Bunge, M. (2006). Chasing reality. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Bunge, M. (2016). Modes of existence. Review of Metaphysics, 70, 225–234.Google Scholar
  9. Bunge, M. (2017). From a scientific point of view. Tyndall: Cambridge Scholars.Google Scholar
  10. Chomsky, N. (2009). The mysteries of nature. Journal of Philosophy, 106, 167–200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. de la Peña, L., Cetto, A. M., & Valdés-Hernández, A. (2015). The emerging quantum: The physics behind quantum mechanics. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
  12. Duhem, P. (1914). La théorie physique, son objet et sa structure. Lyon: Marcel Rivière.Google Scholar
  13. Hall, R. L. (1995). Geometric spectral inversion. Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and General, 28, 1771–1786.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Husserl, E. (1931). Ideas: General introduction to phenomenology. London: George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
  15. Kuhn, T. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  16. Leibniz, G. (1921). [1765]. Nouveaux Essais sur l’entendement humain. Paris: Flammarion.Google Scholar
  17. Pearl, J. (2009). Causality (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Polya, G. (1945). How to solve it. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Polya, G. (1954). Induction and analogy in mathematics. Volume 1: Preface. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Popper, K. R. (1962). Conjectures and refutations. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  21. Russell, B. (1919). An introduction to mathematical philosophy. London: Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
  22. Sanchez-Langelin, B., & Aspu-Guzik, A. (2018). Inverse molecular design using machine learning. Science, 361, 360–365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Schlosshauer, M. (Ed.). (2011). Elegance and enigma: The quantum interviews. Heidelberg: Springer.Google Scholar
  24. Sun, R. (2008). The cambridge handbook of computational psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Tarski, A. (1956/1933). The concept of truth in formalized languages. In J. H. Woodger (Ed. & Trans.), Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics. Papers From 1923–1928 by Alfred Tarski. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  26. Tarski, A. (1944). The semantic conception of truth and the foundations of semantics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 4, 341–376.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  28. Wolin, S. (2008). Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Zeilinger, A. (2010). [2005]. Dance of the photons. New York: Farrar, Strauss and Giroux.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyMcGill UniversityMontrealCanada

Personalised recommendations