Advertisement

Incompatible models in chemistry: the case of electronegativity

  • Hernán Lucas AccorintiEmail author
Article
  • 41 Downloads

Abstract

During the second half of the nineteenth century, electronegativity (EN) has been one of the most relevant chemical concepts to explain the relationships between chemical substances and their possible reactions. Specifically, EN is a property of the substances that allows them to attract external electrons in bonding situations. The problem arises because EN cannot be measured directly. Indeed, the only way to measure it is through different properties that do can be directly measured, for instance enthalpy, ionization energies or electron affinities. What is particularly troubling about this case in quantum chemistry is that the different models used to describe and quantify EN are incompatible but, in a certain sense, equivalent because the same EN scale results in all of them. By analyzing Linus Pauling’s and Robert Mulliken’s models of EN, it will be argued that, if we remain cling to a traditional representative conception of models, we cannot understand the meaning of the information provided by those models. Indeed, if we do not want to adopt an instrumentalist point of view concerning chemical knowledge, we should reconsider by virtue of what a model represents the system, or, in other words, which the factors that determine the representative power of a model are. I will propose a new perspective that incorporates the role of experimental techniques in the very notion of representation; this perspective allows us to understand how supposedly incompatible models of the same target system can be both simultaneously representative.

Keywords

Electronegativity Scientific representation Incompatible models Mulliken’s models Pauling’s models 

Notes

References

  1. Accorinti, H., Martínez González, J.C.: Acerca de la independencia de los modelos respecto de las teorías. Theoria 31, 225–245 (2016)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Allred, A.L.: Electronegativity values from thermochemical data. J. Inorg. Nucl. Chem. 17, 215–221 (1961)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Boeyens, J.C., du Toit, J.: The theoretical basis of electronegativity. Electron. J. Theor. Chem. 2, 296–301 (1997)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bueno, O.: Empirical adequacy: a partial structures approach. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part A 28, 585–610 (1997)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bueno, O., French, S., Ladyman, J.: On representing the relationship between the mathematical and the empirical. Philos. Sci. 69, 452–473 (2002)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Carnap R.: Empiricism, semantics and ontology. Reprinted in the Supplement to Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1950)Google Scholar
  7. Cartwright, N., Shomar, T., Suárez, M.: The tool box of science. In: Herfel, W., Krajewski, W., Niniiluoto, I., Wójcicki, R. (eds.) Theories and Models in Scientific Processes, Poznań Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, pp. 137–149. Rodopi, Amsterdam (1995)Google Scholar
  8. Da Costa, N., French, S.: Models, theories, and structures: thirty years on. Philos. Sci. 67, 116–127 (2000)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Da Costa, N., French, S.: Science and Partial Truth: A Unitary Approach to Models and Scientific Reasoning. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Dunn, J.M.: Relevant predication: intrinsic properties and internal relations. Philos. Stud. 60, 177–206 (1990)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fischer, G.: Content, design, and representation in chemistry. Found. Chem. 19, 17–28 (2017)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Frigg, R.: Models and fiction. Synthese 172, 251–268 (2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Frigg, R.: Models and representation: why structures are not enough. In: Measurement in Physics and Economics Project Discussion Paper Series. DP MEAS 25/02. London School of Economics, London (2002)Google Scholar
  14. Frigg, R.: Scientific representation and the semantic view of theories. Theoria 55, 46–65 (2006)Google Scholar
  15. Giere, R.: How models are used to represent physical reality. Philos. Sci. 71, 742–752 (2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Giere, R.: An agent-based conception of models and scientific representation. Synthese 172, 269–281 (2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Giere, R.: Representing with physical models. In: Humphreys, P., Imbert, C. (eds.) Models, Simulations and Representations, pp. 209–215. Routledge, New York (2011)Google Scholar
  18. Hughes, R.I.G.: Models and representation. Philos. Sci. 64, S325–S336 (1997)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Jensen, W.B.: Electronegativity from Avogadro to Pauling. Part I: origins of the electronegativity concept. J. Chem. Educ. 73, 11–20 (1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Jensen, W.B.: Electronegativity from Avogadro to Pauling: II. Late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century developments. J. Chem. Educ. 80, 279–287 (2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Langton, R., Lewis, D.: Defining ‘intrinsic’. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 58, 333–345 (1998)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Lewis, D.: Extrinsic properties. Philos. Stud. 44, 197–200 (1983)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Lombardi, O., Labarca, M.: The ontological autonomy of the chemical world. Found. Chem. 7(2), 125–148 (2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Marshall, D., Weatherson, B.: Intrinsic vs. extrinsic properties. In: E. N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/intrinsic-extrinsic/ (2018). Accessed 21 Jan 2018
  25. Morrison, M.: One phenomenon, many models: inconsistency and complementarity. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 42, 342–351 (2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Mulliken, R.: A new electroaffinity scale; together with data on valence states and on valence ionization potentials and electron affinities. J. Chem. Phys. 2, 782–793 (1934)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Pauling, L.: The nature of the chemical bond. IV. The energy of single bonds and the relative electronegativity of atoms. J. Am. Chem. Soc. 54, 3570–3582 (1932)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Pauling, L.: College Chemistry: An Introductory Textbook of General Chemistry, 2nd edn. W. H. Freeman & Company, San Francisco (1950)Google Scholar
  29. Putnam, H.: Reason, Truth and History. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1981)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Ruthenberg, K., Martínez González, J.C.: Electronegativity and its multiple faces: persistence and measurement. Found. Chem. 19, 61–75 (2017)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Sanderson, R.T.: Chemical Bonds and bond Energy, 2nd edn. Academic Press, New York (1976)Google Scholar
  32. Sider, T.: Intrinsic properties. Philos. Stud. 83, 1–27 (1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Suárez, M.: The role of models in the application of scientific theories: epistemological implications. In: Morgan, M., Morrison, M. (eds.) Models as Mediators, pp. 168–196. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1999)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Suárez, M.: Scientific representation: against similarity and isomorphism. Int. Stud. Philos. Sci. 17, 225–244 (2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Suárez, M.: An inferential conception of scientific representation. Philos. Sci. 71, 767–779 (2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Suárez, M.: Fictions in Science: Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealization. Routledge, New York (2009)Google Scholar
  37. Suárez, M.: Scientific realism, the Galilean strategy and representation. In: González, W. (ed.) Scientific Realism and Democratic Society: The Philosophy of Philip Kitcher. Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, pp. 269–292. Rodopi, Amsterdam (2012)Google Scholar
  38. Suárez, M., Cartwright, N.: Theories: tools versus models. Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 39, 62–81 (2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Vallentyne, P.: Intrinsic properties defined. Philos. Stud. 88, 209–219 (1997)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Wells, P.R.: Group electronegativities. In: Streitwieser Jr., A., Taft, R.W. (eds.) Progress in Physical Organic Chemistry, pp. 111–145. Wiley, Berkeley (1968)Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.FONCYT-Universidad de Buenos AiresBuenos AiresArgentina

Personalised recommendations