Advertisement

Erkenntnis

pp 1–14 | Cite as

On the Proper Treatment of the Churchlands

  • Serdal TümkayaEmail author
Original Research

Abstract

To a significant extent, mainstream Western philosophy is not empirically minded. The neurophilosophy of the Churchlands seems to exhibit the greatest divergence from this orientation by far. Extending and neuralizing Quine’s naturalism, the Churchlands have been known to challenge most assumptions and principles of contemporary mainstream analytic and even existing naturalistic philosophies. Even the philosophers who identify themselves as full-blown naturalists have an inexplicably negative attitude toward the Churchlands. For many philosophers of the mind, the Churchlands’ problem is not that they are philosophically wrong, but that they have no philosophical approach that could be wrong. They are nonphilosophers working at philosophy departments. Proper philosophy is not what they do or think they are doing. In this article, I argue to the contrary. The Churchlands would seem surprisingly moderate, and neither trivial nor near-trivial, when closely scrutinized.

Notes

References

  1. Allen-Hermanson, S. (2015). Strong neurophilosophy and the matter of bat consciousness: A case study. Erkenntnis, 80(1), 57–76.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-014-9612-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bickle, J. (1992). Revisionary physicalism. Biology and Philosophy, 7(4), 411–430.  https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00130060.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bickle, J. (2018). Lessons for experimental philosophy from the rise and “fall” of neurophilosophy. Philosophical Psychology.  https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2018.1512705.Google Scholar
  4. Bickle, J., Mandik, P., & Landreth, A. (2012). The Philosophy of Neuroscience. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 201). Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/neuroscience/. Accessed 29 Mar 2019.
  5. Churchland, P. M. (1979). Scientific realism and the plasticity of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. The Journal of Philosophy, 78(2), 67–90.  https://doi.org/10.2307/2025900.Google Scholar
  7. Churchland, P. S. (1983). Consciousness: The transmutation of a concept. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 80–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Churchland, P. S. (1986a). Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind-brain. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  9. Churchland, P. S. (1986b). Replies to comments. Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 29(1–4), 241–272.  https://doi.org/10.1080/00201748608602089.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Churchland, P. M. (1988). Matter and consciousness: A contemporary introduction to the philosophy of mind (Revised). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  11. Churchland, P. M. (1994). Folk psychology (2). In S. Guttenplan (Ed.), A companion to the philosophy of mind (pp. 308–316). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  12. Churchland, P. M. (1998a). Folk psychology. On the contrary: Critical essays, 1987–1997 (pp. 3–15). Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Churchland, P. M. (1998b). Replies. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58(4), 893–904.  https://doi.org/10.2307/2653731.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Churchland, P. M. (1998c). Reply to glymor. On the contrary: Critical essays, 1987–1997 (pp. 280–287). Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Churchland, P. S. (2002). Brain-wise: Studies in neurophilosophy. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  16. Churchland, P. S. (2007). Neurophilosophy: The early years and new directions. Functional Neurology, 22(4), 185–195.Google Scholar
  17. Churchland, P. S., & Churchland, P. M. (1996). Do we propose to eliminate consciousness? In R. N. McCauley (Ed.), The churchlands and their critics (pp. 297–300). Cambridge: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  18. Churchland, P. M., & Churchland, P. S. (1998). Intertheoretic reduction: A neuroscientist’s field guide. In Y. Christen & P. Churchland (Eds.), Neurophilosophy and alzheimer’s disease (pp. 65–79). Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  19. Floridi, L. (2017). A plea for non-naturalism as constructionism. Minds and Machines, 27(2), 269–285.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-017-9422-9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Fodor, J. (1990). Making mind matter more. In A theory of content and other essays (pp. 137–159). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  21. Gold, I., & Stoljar, D. (1999). A neuron doctrine in the philosophy of neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(05), 809–830.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Klagge, J. C. (1989). Wittgenstein and neuroscience. Synthese, 78(3), 319–343.  https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00869353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Lelling, A. E. (1993). Eliminative materialism, neuroscience and the criminal law. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 141(4), 1471–1564.  https://doi.org/10.2307/3312346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. McGinn, C. (1989). Can we solve the mind-body problem? Mind, 98(391), 349–366.  https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/XCVIII.391.349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. McGinn, C. (2014). Review of touching a nerve (storm over the brain). The New York Review of Books. Retrieved from http://www.nybooks.com/articles/2014/04/24/storm-over-the-brain/. Accessed 29 Mar 2019.
  26. Mölder, B., & Churchland, P. S. (2015). Neuroscience is relevant for philosophy. Problemos, 88, 176–186.  https://doi.org/10.15388/Problemos.2015.88.8487.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Morris, S. (2018). Scientific philosophy and the critique of metaphysics from russell to carnap to quine. Erkenntnis.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0049-x.Google Scholar
  28. Noë, A. (2003). Towards a biology of the mind. Nature, 423(6942), 805.  https://doi.org/10.1038/423805a.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Northoff, G. (2004a). Philosophy of the brain: The brain problem. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Northoff, G. (2004b). What is neurophilosophy? A methodological account. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 35, 91–127.  https://doi.org/10.1023/B:JGPS.0000035153.89143.4c.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Northoff, G. (2011). Neuropsychoanalysis in Practice: Brain, self and objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Northoff, G. (2014a). Minding the brain: A guide to philosophy and neuroscience. London: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Northoff, G. (2014b). Unlocking the brain: Volume 1: Coding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  34. Northoff, G. (2016). Neuro-philosophy of the healthy mind: Learning from the unwell brain. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
  35. Northoff, G. (2018). The spontaneous brain: From the mind-body to the world-brain problem. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Quine, W. V. O. (1948). On what there is. The Review of Metaphysics, 2(5), 21–38.Google Scholar
  37. Rorty, R. (1970). Incorrigibility as the mark of the mental. Journal of Philosophy, 67(12), 399–424.  https://doi.org/10.2307/2024002.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Smith, P. (1982). Eliminative materialism—a reply to everitt. Mind, XCI(363), 438–440.  https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/XCI.363.438.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Wilkes, K. V. (1991). The relationship between scientific psychology and common-sense psychology. Synthese, 89(1), 15–39.  https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00413797.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Williams, D. (1962). Notices of recent publications: Neurophilosophy. Brain, 85(1), 166–167.  https://doi.org/10.1093/brain/85.1.166-a.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy DepartmentMiddle East Technical University (METU)AnkaraTurkey

Personalised recommendations