Advertisement

The Coherence of Evolutionary Theory with Its Neighboring Theories

  • Seungbae ParkEmail author
Regular Article
  • 22 Downloads

Abstract

Evolutionary theory coheres with its neighboring theories, such as the theory of plate tectonics, molecular biology, electromagnetic theory, and the germ theory of disease. These neighboring theories were previously unconceived, but they were later conceived, and then they cohered with evolutionary theory. Since evolutionary theory has been strengthened by its several neighboring theories that were previously unconceived, it will be strengthened by infinitely many hitherto unconceived neighboring theories. This argument for evolutionary theory echoes the problem of unconceived alternatives. Ironically, however, the former recommends that we take the realist attitude toward evolutionary theory, while the latter recommends that we take the antirealist attitude toward it.

Keywords

Coherence Evolutionary theory Joint explanation Unconceived neighboring theories 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to the two anonymous referees of this journal for sharp comments. This work was supported by the Ministry of Education of the Republic of Korea and the National Research Foundation of Korea (NRF-2016S1A5A2A01022592).

References

  1. Chakravartty A (2008) What you don’t know can’t hurt you: realism and the unconceived. Philos Stud 137(1):149–158Google Scholar
  2. Datta-Roy A, Praveen Karanth K (2009) The out-of india hypothesis: What do molecules suggest? J Biosci 34(5):687–697Google Scholar
  3. Devitt M (2011) Are unconceived alternatives a problem for scientific realism? J Gen Philos Sci 42(2):285–293Google Scholar
  4. Doppelt G (2007) Reconstructing scientific realism to rebut the pessimistic meta-induction. Philos Sci 74(1):96–118Google Scholar
  5. Doppelt G (2011) From standard scientific realism and structural realism to best current theory realism. J Gen Philos Sci 42(2):295–316Google Scholar
  6. Doppelt G (2014) Best theory scientific realism. Eur J Philos Sci 4(2):271–291Google Scholar
  7. Enfield P (2008) Review of P. Kyle Stanford’s exceeding our grasp: science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Br J Philos Sci 59(4):881–895Google Scholar
  8. Fahrbach L (2011a) How the growth of science ends theory change. Synthese 180(2):139–155Google Scholar
  9. Fahrbach L (2011b) Theory change and degrees of success. Philos Sci 78(5):1283–1292Google Scholar
  10. Friedman M (1981) Theoretical explanation. In: Healey R (ed) Reduction, time, and reality: studies in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  11. Godfrey-Smith P (2008) Recurrent transient underdetermination and the glass half full. Philos Stud 137:141–148Google Scholar
  12. Harker D (2008) P. Kyle Stanford, exceeding our grasp: science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Philos Sci 75(2):251–253Google Scholar
  13. Hempel C (1966) Philosophy of natural science. Prentice-Hall Inc., Englewood CliffsGoogle Scholar
  14. Jablonski N, Chaplin G (2010) Human skin pigmentation as an adaptation to UV radiation. Proc Natl Acad Sci 107(2):8968–9862Google Scholar
  15. Kitcher P (1993) The advancement of science: science without legend, objectivity without illusion. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  16. Kowalski W (2009) Ultraviolet germicidal irradiation handbook: UVGI for air and surface disinfection. Springer, Berlin.  https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-01999-9 Google Scholar
  17. Kuhn T (1962/1970) The structure of scientific revolutions, 2nd ed. The University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  18. Kumazawa Y, Nishida M (2000) Molecular phylogeny of osteoglossoids: a new model for gondwanian origin and plate tectonic transportation of the Asian Arowana. Mol Biol Evol 17(12):1869–1878Google Scholar
  19. Laudan L (1981) A confutation of convergent realism. Philos Sci 48(1):19–49Google Scholar
  20. Leplin J (1997) A novel defense of scientific realism. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  21. Mizrahi M (2013) The pessimistic induction: a bad argument gone too far. Synthese 190(15):3209–3226Google Scholar
  22. Musgrave A (1985) Realism versus constructive empiricism. In: Churchland PM, Hooker CA (eds) Images of science: essays on realism and empiricism. The University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  23. Park S (2011a) Coherence of our best scientific theories. Found Sci 16(1):21–30Google Scholar
  24. Park S (2011b) A confutation of the pessimistic induction. J Gen Philos Sci 42(1):75–84Google Scholar
  25. Park S (2015) Accepting our best scientific theories. Filos Soc 26(3):218–227Google Scholar
  26. Park S (2016) Refutations of the two pessimistic inductions. Philosophia 44(3):835–844Google Scholar
  27. Park S (2017a) Why should we be pessimistic about antirealists and pessimists? Found Sci 22(3):613–625Google Scholar
  28. Park S (2017b) Selective realism versus individual realism for scientific creativity. Creat Stud 10(1):97–107Google Scholar
  29. Park S (2017c) On treating past and present scientific theories differently. Kriterion 31(1):63–75Google Scholar
  30. Park S (2018a) Justifying the special theory of relativity with unconceived methods. Axiomathes 28(1):53–62Google Scholar
  31. Park S (2018b) Optimistic realism over selectivism. Kriter J Philos (to be assigned)Google Scholar
  32. Park S (2018c) The anti-induction for scientific realism. Grazer Philos Stud 95(3):329–342Google Scholar
  33. Park S (2018d) The grand pessimistic induction. Rev Contemp Philos 17:7–19Google Scholar
  34. Park S (2019) New objections to the problem of unconceived alternatives. Filos Unis 20(2) (to be assigned)Google Scholar
  35. Psillos S (1999) Scientific realism: how science tracks truth. Routledge, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  36. Psillos S (2009) Grasping at realist straws. Rev Symp Metasci 18:363–370Google Scholar
  37. Psillos S (2018) Tolstoy’s argument: realism and the history of science. Spontan Gen A J Hist Philos Sci 9(1):68–76Google Scholar
  38. Putnam H (1975) Mathematics, matter and method (Philosophical Papers, vo. 1). Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  39. Ruhmkorff S (2011) Some difficulties for the problem of unconceived alternative. Philos Sci 78(5):875–886Google Scholar
  40. Ruhmkorff S (2013) Global and local pessimistic meta-inductions. Int Stud Philos Sci 27(4):409–428Google Scholar
  41. Saatsi J (2009) Grasping at realist straws. Rev Symp Metasci 18:355–362Google Scholar
  42. Soucy S, Huang J, Gogarten J (2015) Horizontal gene transfer: building the web of life. Nat Rev Genet 16:472–482Google Scholar
  43. Stanford PK (2006) Exceeding our grasp: science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  44. Stanford PK (2018) A fond farewell to ‘approximate truth’? Spontan Gen A J Hist Philos Sci 9(1):78–91Google Scholar
  45. The Huntington’s Disease Collaborative Research Group (1993) A novel gene containing a trinucleotide repeat that is expanded and unstable on huntington’s disease chromosomes. Cell 72:971–983Google Scholar
  46. Trefil J, Hazen RM (1998) The sciences: an integrated approach. Wiley, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  47. Vickers P (2017) Understanding the selective realist defence against the PMI. Synthese 194(9):3221–3232Google Scholar
  48. Woodburne M, Zinsmeister W (1982) Fossil land mammal from Antarctica. Science 218:284–286Google Scholar
  49. Worrall J (1989) Structural realism: the best of both worlds. Dialectica 43:99–124Google Scholar
  50. Wray KB (2013) The pessimistic induction and the exponential growth of science reassessed. Synthese 190(18):4321–4330Google Scholar
  51. Wray KB (2016) Method and continuity in science. J Gen Philos Sci 47(2):363–375Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Ulsan National Institute of Science and TechnologyUlsanRepublic of Korea

Personalised recommendations