Skip to main content

Metaphor in Chemistry: An Examination of Chemical Metaphor

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Philosophy of Chemistry

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 306))

Abstract

The function of metaphor in science has been labeled as decorative, persuasive, heuristic, instrumental, facilitating or obstructing. It has sometimes been regarded as inspiring, provoking, perverting or destroying rational thought. Metaphor’s positive role has been noted by philosophers, historians of chemistry, and science education researchers. It has been hailed as a descriptive and explanatory device that stimulates and shapes concept development. I discuss how metaphor functions in science generally, then refine this idea through an examination metaphor’s role in chemical thinking in three contexts: the history and philosophy of chemistry, laboratory research practice, and chemical education. I aim to show how metaphor is already operative in the chemist’s use of the concept of chemical element and that this understanding characterizes chemical thinking in general. The chapter concludes with a discussion of a specifically chemical understanding of metaphor.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    T. Nummedal (2011), Bensaude-Vincent and Stengers (1996), Newman and Principe (1998), Dobbs (2002), Merchant (1980), and others.

  2. 2.

    Jeppsson et al. (2013), Aubusson et al. (2006), Tobin and Tippins (1996), Hofmann (1990) and others.

  3. 3.

    Black (1962), Cassirer (1953), Hesse (1966, 1988), Harré and Martin (1982), among others.

  4. 4.

    This is, in fact, what Cassirer (1953) called “radical metaphor” and Kuhn (1977; 1979) referred to as “metaphor-like processes.” This theme is discussed in depth in Sects. 9.5 and 9.6 below.

  5. 5.

    The National Science Foundation and other science agencies have sought to dispel institutional tendencies to polarize the two modes of practice by issuing funding solicitations that call for integrative undergraduate science curricula. For example the NSF’s Undergraduate Research Centers.

  6. 6.

    See Graves’ (2005) treatment of this theme in Sect. 9.4, and Bhushan and Rosenfeld’s (1995) treatment in Sect. 9.5, below.

  7. 7.

    As the story goes, a visiting physicist commented on a horseshoe hanging above the doorway of Bohr’s country home, “Bohr, I didn’t know you believed in such superstitions!” to which Bohr responded: “I don’t, but I’ve heard that it works whether or not one believes in it.”

  8. 8.

    As does Ian Hacking’s (1983) Representing and Intervening.

  9. 9.

    A full discussion of the development of this definition and its impact on chemical research and education appears Sect. 9.6 of this chapter.

  10. 10.

    See, among others, Earley (2009), Harré (2010), Mahootian (2013), Ruthenberg (2009), and Scerri (2000, 2005, 2009), and of course Paneth (1931/1962), who originated this definition.

  11. 11.

    It was translated into English for publication in 1962 as “The epistemological status of the chemical concept of element” in British Journal of the Philosophy of Science. 13, 1–14 and 144–160; it was reprinted in Foundations of Chemistry 5, 2003, 113–145.

  12. 12.

    Analytic philosopher, Max Black (1962) applied rhetoric theoretician I.A. Richards’ interaction theory of metaphor in this manner. Kuang-Ming Wu’s (2001) cross-cultural hermeneutic approach to metaphor affirms this point with examples from several contexts and languages.

  13. 13.

    Nye completely excludes alchemy from her account—this is an important omission that follows in the steps of nineteenth and early twentieth century historiography of science. I. Stengers and B. Bensaude-Vincent’s History of Chemistry, published only a few years after Nye (1994), showed how fundamental concepts of chemistry, such as analysis, isolation and purification were developed to a high degree of sophistication. From the late 1990s to the early 2000s, W. Newman and L. Principe provided a wealth of documentary evidence to support the inclusion of alchemy in the history of chemistry. Tara Nummedal discusses the versatility of alchemy’s promotion of chemistry.

  14. 14.

    The term “like attracts like” still enjoys broad usage ranging from matchmaking websites to titles and abstracts of research articles in academic journals of physics, chemistry and molecular biology.

  15. 15.

    Graves focuses more of her analysis on the lab’s use of metonyms than on metaphors, however, the case has been made in section 1 above, that the various genera of non-literal usages of language actually function metaphorically, even if they are not identical in form to metaphors. Kuhn’s (1977, 1979) and Cassirer’s (1953) discussions of this idea are found in Sects. 9.5 and 9.6, below.

  16. 16.

    Pickering’s seemingly odd choice of this term harks back to old-time clothes washing machines which had no spin cycle. Instead, wet clothing were put through the ringer and the resulting “mangle” consisted of diverse items of damp clothing pressed into a single, flat, apparently continuous plank.

  17. 17.

    Fredrik Jeppsson et al. (2013) Exploring the Use of Conceptual Metaphors in Solving Problems on Entropy, Journal of the Learning Sciences, 22:1, 70–120.

  18. 18.

    See Jeppsson et al. (2013, 72).

  19. 19.

    Jeppsson et al. (2013, 72).

  20. 20.

    In three volumes (1925–1929) Yale University Press. Cassirer draws on a broad multidisciplinary pool of evidence from human, social and physical science of the mid-twentieth century.

  21. 21.

    Mahootian 2013 “Paneth’s epistemology of chemical elements in light of Kant’s Opus postumum.” Foundations of Chemistry 15:171–184.

  22. 22.

    As found for example in Lakoff and Johnson (2008).

  23. 23.

    Metonymy is a specific kind of metaphor that makes a part, or aspect, stand for the whole e.g., saying “friends, Romans, countrymen, lend me your ears.”

  24. 24.

    Harré 2010, Causal concepts in chemical vernaculars. Foundations of Chemistry 12:101–115

References

  • Aubusson P, Harrison AG, Ritchie S (eds) (2006) Metaphor and analogy in science education (Vol. 30). Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailer-Jones DM (2000) Scientific models as metaphors. In: Hallyn F (ed) Metaphor and analogy in the sciences. Springer, Netherlands, pp 181–198

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bailer-Jones DM (2002) Models, metaphors and analogies. In: Machamer P (ed) The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of science. Blackwell, New York, pp 108–127

    Google Scholar 

  • Bensaude-Vincent B, Stengers I (1996) A history of chemistry. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Black M (1962) Models and metaphors: studies in language and philosophy. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N (1983) How the laws of physics lie. Clarendon, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer E (1953) Language and myth. Dover Publications, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobbs BJT (2002) The Janus faces of genius: the role of alchemy in Newton’s thought. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Earley JE Sr (2009) How chemistry shifts horizons: element, substance, and the essential. Found Chem 11:65–77

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Graves H (2005) Rhetoric in(to) science: style as invention in inquiry. Hampton Press, Cresskill

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (1983) Representing and intervening. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harré R, Martin J (1982) Metaphor in science. In: Miall D (ed) Metaphor: problems and perspectives. Humanities, Atlantic Highlands

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré R (2010) Causal concepts in chemical vernaculars. Found Chem 12:101–115

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hesse MB (1966) Models and analogies in science. Notre Dame University Press, Notre Dame

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse MB (1980) Revolutions and reconstructions in the philosophy of science. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse MB (1988) The cognitive claims of metaphor. J Specul Philos 2:1–16

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofmann JR (1990) How the models of chemistry vie. In: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Philosophy of Science Association, pp 405–419

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeppsson F, Haglund J, Amin TG, Strmdahl H (2013) Exploring the use of conceptual metaphors in solving problems on Entropy. J Learn Sci 22(1):70–120

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1962) The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1977) Second thoughts on paradigms. In: Suppes P (ed) The structure of scientific theories. University of Illinois Press, Urbana, pp 459–483

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1979) Metaphor in science. In: Ortony A (ed) Metaphor and thought. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 533–542

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff G, Johnson M (2008) Metaphors we live by. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahootian F (2013) Paneth’s epistemology of chemical elements in light of Kant’s Opus postumum. Found Chem 15(2):171–184, Chicago: Springer

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Martin J, Harré R (1982) Metaphor in science. In: Miall DS (ed) Metaphor: problems and perspectives. The Harvester Press, Sussex, pp 89–105

    Google Scholar 

  • Merchant C (1980) The death of nature: women, ecology, and the scientific revolution. Harper Collins, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller AI (1996) Insights of genius: imagery and creativity in science and art. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Newman WR, Principe LM (1998) Alchemy vs. chemistry: the etymological origins of a historiographic mistake1. Early Sci Med 3(1):32–65

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Nummedal TE (2011) Words and works in the history of alchemy. Isis 102(2):330–337

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nye MJ (1994) From chemical philosophy to theoretical chemistry: dynamics of matter and dynamics of disciplines, 1800–1950. University of California Press, Los Angeles

    Google Scholar 

  • Paneth FA (1962/2003) The epistemological status of the chemical concept of element. Br J Philos Sci 13:1–14, 144–160 (This was reprinted in Foundations of Chemistry, 5, 2003, 113–145. Kluwer, The Netherlands)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickering A (1984) Constructing quarks: a sociological history of particle physics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Pickering A (1995) The mangle of practice: time, agency, and science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur P (1981) The rule of metaphor: multi-disciplinary studies of the creation of meaning in language. University of Toronto Press, Toronto

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruthenberg K (2009) Paneth, Kant, and the philosophy of chemistry. Found Chem 11:79–91

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Scerri ER (2000) Realism, reduction and the ‘intermediate position’. In: Bhushan N, Rosenfeld S (eds) Of minds and molecules. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 51–72

    Google Scholar 

  • Scerri ER (2005) Some aspects of the metaphysics of chemistry and the nature of the elements. Hyle 11:127–145

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Scerri ER (2009) The dual sense of the term “element”, attempts to derive the Madelung rule, and the optimal form of the periodic table, if any. Int J Quantum Chem 109(5):959–971

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Tobin K, Tippins DJ (1996) Metaphors as seeds for conceptual change and the improvement of science teaching. Sci Educ 80(6):711–730

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead AN (1938) Modes of thought. McMillan Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wu KM (2001) On metaphoring: a cultural hermeneutic. Brill, Boston

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Farzad Mahootian .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mahootian, F. (2015). Metaphor in Chemistry: An Examination of Chemical Metaphor. In: Scerri, E., McIntyre, L. (eds) Philosophy of Chemistry. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 306. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9364-3_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics