Skip to main content
Log in

“How powerful is demography? The serendipity theorem revisited” comment on De la Croix et al. (2012)

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Population Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Samuelson’s (Int Econ Rev 16(3):531-538, 1975) serendipity theorem states that the “goldenest golden rule” steady-state equilibrium can be obtained by a competitive two-period overlapping generation economy with capital accumulation, provided that the optimal growth rate prevails. De la Croix et al. (J Popul Econ 25:899-922, 2012) extended the scope of the theorem by showing that it also holds for risky lifetime. With this note, we introduce medical expenditure as a determinant of the probability of surviving to old age to prove the theorem. The original as well as all extended versions of the serendipity theorem, however, fail to prove that second-order conditions are satisfied in general. Still, unlike De la Croix et al. (J Popul Econ 25:899-922, 2012), we can exclude the existence of corner solutions where the probability of reaching old age is zero or one. The zero survival probability case becomes irrelevant if the option to randomize between death and life utility is taken into account. Survival with certainty is ruled out if the marginal cost of survival is increasing. Hence, the optimal survival probability represents an interior solution. Furthermore, we show for the optimal survival probability that the value of a statistical life is positive and equal to its marginal cost.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Chakraborty (2004) introduced this specification to analyze the relationship between endogenous lifetime and economic growth. De la Croix and Ponthière (2010) used it to address the optimal accumulation of capital under endogenous longevity. Felder and Mayrhofer (2011) applied this specification in a one-period of life model to derive optimal investment in longevity.

  2. Beside the basic model with consumption in the first- and the second period of life, De la Croix et al. (2013) incorporated exogenous old-age labor and endogenous labor supply. Schweizer (1996, p. 210) criticized the quest for extended versions of the serendipity theorem: “It might be fun to derive serendipity type and Henry George type results for general settings. The more tedious task, however, which consists of ensuring a maximum rather than a minimum of well-being should always be kept in mind.”

  3. See the Appendix for the derivation of the second-order conditions.

  4. In the industrialized world, the median public share of total health spending is 71.5 % (OECD 2014).

References

  • Abio G (2003) Interiority of the optimal population growth rate with endogenous fertility. Econ Bull 10(4):1–7

  • Chakraborty S (2004) Endogenous lifetime and economic growth. J Econ Theory 116:119–137

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De la Croix D, Ponthière G (2010) On the golden rule of capital accumulation under endogenous longevity. Math Soc Sci 59(2):227–238

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De la Croix D, Pestieau P, Ponthière G (2012) How powerful is demography? The serendipity theorem revisited. J Popul Econ 25:899–922

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deardorff AV (1976) The optimum growth rate for population: comment. Int Econ Rev 17(2):510–515

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felder S, Mayrhofer T (2011) Medical decision making: a health economic primer. Springer, Heidelberg

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hall RE, Jones CI (2007) The value of life and the rise in health spending. Q J Econ 122(1):39–72

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaeger K, Kuhle W (2009) The optimum growth rate for population reconsidered. J Popul Econ 22(1):23–41

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michel P, Pestieau P (1993) Population growth and optimality: when does the serendipity theorem hold? J Popul Econ 6(4):353–362

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy KM, Topel RH (2006) The value of health and longevity. J Polit Econ 114(5):871–904

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • OECD (2014) Health statistics. Paris

  • Rosen S (1988) The value of changes in life expectancy. J Risk Uncertain 1:285–304

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson PA (1958) An exact consumption-loan model of interest with or without the social contrivance of money. J Polit Econ 66(6):467–482

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson PA (1975) The optimum growth rate for population. Int Econ Rev 16(3):531–538

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schweizer U (1996) Endogenous fertility and the Henry George theorem. J Publ Econ 61:209–228

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi WK, Aldy JE (2003) The value of saving a life: a critical review of market estimates throughout the world. J Risk Uncertain 27(1):5–76

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I wish to thank Friedrich Breyer for most helpful comments and Denis Bieri for technical assistance. Comments by two referees are also gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stefan Felder.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Responsible editor: Alessandro Cigno

Appendix

Appendix

If we assume that the population growth rate is exogenous, three first-order conditions remain for the planner’s problem, Eqs. (3), (4), and (12) in the model with costly survival. Substituting the resource constraint (11) for c, the Hessian matrix of the second-order derivatives associated with this problem is

$$ H=\left[\begin{array}{ccc}\hfill \frac{\partial^2\mathrm{E}\mathrm{U}}{\partial {d}^2}\hfill & \hfill \frac{\partial^2\mathrm{E}\mathrm{U}}{\partial d\partial k}\hfill & \hfill \frac{\partial^2\mathrm{E}\mathrm{U}}{\partial d\partial m}\hfill \\ {}\hfill \frac{\partial^2\mathrm{E}\mathrm{U}}{\partial k\partial d}\hfill & \hfill \frac{\partial^2\mathrm{E}\mathrm{U}}{\partial {k}^2}\hfill & \hfill \frac{\partial^2\mathrm{E}\mathrm{U}}{\partial k\partial m}\hfill \\ {}\hfill \frac{\partial^2\mathrm{E}\mathrm{U}}{\partial m\partial d}\hfill & \hfill \frac{\partial^2\mathrm{E}\mathrm{U}}{\partial m\partial k}\hfill & \hfill \frac{\partial^2\mathrm{E}\mathrm{U}}{\partial {m}^2}\hfill \end{array}\right] $$

Hence, \( \left[\begin{array}{ccc}\hfill {\left[\frac{\pi (m)}{1+n}\right]}^2u^{\prime\prime }(c)+\pi (m)u^{\prime\prime }(d)\hfill & \hfill -u^{\prime\prime }(c)\left(f^{\prime }(k)-n\right)\frac{\pi (m)}{1+n}\hfill & \hfill \begin{array}{l}u^{\prime\prime }(c)\frac{\pi (m)}{{\left(1+n\right)}^2}\left[1+n+\pi^{\prime }(m)d\right]\\ {}-u^{\prime }(c)\frac{\pi^{\prime }(m)}{1+n}+u^{\prime }(d)\pi^{\prime }(m)\end{array}\hfill \\ {}\hfill -u^{\prime\prime }(c)\left(f^{\prime }(k)-n\right)\frac{\pi (m)}{1+n}\hfill & \hfill \begin{array}{l}u^{\prime\prime }(c){\left[\left(f\prime (k)-n\right)\right]}^2\\ {}+u^{\prime }(c)f^{\prime\prime }(k)\end{array}\hfill & \hfill -\frac{u^{\prime\prime }(c)}{1+n}\left[1+n+\pi^{\prime }(m)d\right]\left({f}^{\prime }(k)-n\right)\hfill \\ {}\hfill \begin{array}{l}u^{\prime\prime }(c)\frac{\pi (m)}{{\left(1+n\right)}^2}\left[1+n+\pi^{\prime }(m)d\right]\\ {}-u^{\prime }(c)\frac{\pi^{\prime }(m)}{1+n}+{u}^{\prime }(d){\pi}^{\prime }(m)\end{array}\hfill & \hfill -\frac{u^{\prime\prime }(c)}{1+n}\left(f^{\prime }(k)-n\right)\left[1+n+\pi^{\prime }(m)d\right]\hfill & \hfill \begin{array}{l}\frac{u^{\prime\prime }(c)}{{\left(1+n\right)}^2}{\left[1+n+\pi \prime (m)d\right]}^2\\ {}-u^{\prime }(c)\frac{\pi^{\prime\prime }(m)d}{1+n}+\pi^{\prime\prime }(m)u(d)\end{array}\hfill \end{array}\right] \) Substituting the first-order conditions yields

$$ \left[\begin{array}{ccc}\hfill {\left[\frac{\pi (m)}{1+n}\right]}^2u^{\prime\prime }(c)+\pi (m)u^{\prime\prime }(d)\hfill & \hfill 0\hfill & \hfill u^{\prime\prime }(c)\frac{\pi (m)}{{\left(1+n\right)}^2}\frac{\pi^{\prime }(m)u(d)}{u^{\prime }(d)}\hfill \\ {}\hfill 0\hfill & \hfill u^{\prime }(c)f^{\prime \prime }(k)\hfill & \hfill 0\hfill \\ {}\hfill u^{\prime\prime }(c)\frac{\pi (m)}{{\left(1+n\right)}^2}\frac{\pi^{\prime }(m)u(d)}{u^{\prime }(d)}\hfill & \hfill 0\hfill & \hfill \frac{u^{\prime\prime }(c)}{{\left(1+n\right)}^2}{\left[\frac{\pi \prime (m)u(d)}{u\prime (d)}\right]}^2+u^{\prime }(c)\frac{\pi^{\prime\prime }(m)}{\pi^{\prime }(m)}\hfill \end{array}\right] $$

A sufficient condition for (c, d, k, m) to be a maximum is that the Hessian matrix is negative definite. The second-order conditions (19)–(21) in the text are the three conditions concerning the determinants of the three submatrices of size 1 × 1, 2 × 2, and 3 × 3 that guarantee the negative definiteness of H.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Felder, S. “How powerful is demography? The serendipity theorem revisited” comment on De la Croix et al. (2012). J Popul Econ 29, 957–967 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00148-016-0587-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00148-016-0587-y

Keywords

JEL classification

Navigation